Navigation – Plan du site

AccueilNuméros14-2Recent Shifts in the Boundaries o...Looking for a “Genuine Science of...

Recent Shifts in the Boundaries of Economics: Philosophy and History

Looking for a “Genuine Science of Politics.” William H. Riker and the Game Theoretical Turn in Political Science

À la recherche d’une « véritable science du politique ». William H. Riker et l’introduction de la théorie des jeux en sciences politique
Gianluca Damiani
p. 149-193

Résumés

Cet article se propose de montrer que le tournant formel en économie a influencé les développements de la théorie du choix rationnel et de la théorie des jeux en science politique. Notre attention se concentre sur le politiste américain William H. Riker (1920-1993). Nous montrons comment Riker a utilisé la théorie des jeux et comment il l’a adaptée aux fins de son agenda disciplinaire, en contre-tendance par rapport au reste de la science politique américaine d’après-guerre. Cet article souhaite montrer que, dans ce processus Riker met en évidence plusieurs aspects de la théorie des jeux qui contrastent nettement avec ceux mis en avant par le programme de recherche de l’économie mathématique d’après-guerre, dont fait partie la théorie des jeux. La section 1 et 2 de l’article décrivent la formation de Riker et sa vie intellectuelle jusqu’à la fin des années 1950, documentant sa rencontre avec la théorie des jeux et montrant les évolutions de la science politique américaine durant cette décennie cruciale. La section 3 présente les principaux arguments de Riker dans The Theory of Political Coalitions, en se concentrant sur son travail de production, via la théorie des jeux, d’un modèle approprié de la construction des coalitions politiques. La section 4 discute certains aspects méthodologiques de l’adhésion de Riker à la théorie des jeux et à l’analyse économique. En particulier, nous souhaitons mettre en évidence et discuter un « dilèmme » apparent, dans la production théorique de Riker, à savoir sa vision dépassée de l’économie malgré son usage de la théorie des jeux.

Haut de page

Texte intégral

1Although game theory now occupies a central role in the toolkit of economic theorists, a remarkable feature of its history is that in the 1950s, 1960s, and 1970s, this approach struggled to enter the economics mainstream. However, in a discipline striving to develop a formal, truly scientific, and possibly unified methodological canon, such as the 1950s political science, the kind of formal theory initially proposed by John von Neumann and Oskar Morgenstern was immediately perceived by some scholars as the ideal toolbox of methods, notions, and techniques. This aspect also points to another remarkable feature of game theory. Namely, it was a tool capable of being exploited across different disciplinary domains other than economics. This article shows that in the 1950s and 1960s, game theory occupied a central place in a definite intellectual agenda, and this was not part of economics but political science instead.

2Such a push for the adoption of game theory outside economics had its roots in some reviews of von Neumann and Morgenstern’s opus (von Neumann and Morgenstern, [1944] 2007) like Herbert Simon’s one (Simon, 1945). For what concerns political science, the 1950s saw some early results obtained through the so-called “cooperative game theory,” like those by the future Nobelist Lloyd Shapley and fellow economist Martin Shubik (Shapley and Shubik, 1954). These must be added to the well-known attempts to use the theory of games in international relations (Kaplan, 1957; Schelling, 1980). However, it was thanks to the commitment of a political scientist, William H. Riker, that game theory became the primary tool of the attempt to develop a truly scientific political science. As Riker wrote in the first chapter of his most ambitious theoretical work, The Theory of Political Coalitions (1962), “the main hope for a genuine science of politics lies in the discovery and use of an adequate model of political behavior” (Riker, 1962, 9). Such a model to him was eminently game-theoretical.

  • 1 Positive Political Theory” was the name adopted by Riker yet in the 1950s. It will later become th (...)

3From Riker’s dedication, a long line of academic research in political science, which he defined as “Positive Political Theory,” was established, where decision theory, game theory, and a rigorous formal fashion in assessing political phenomena represented the methodological canon to be adopted (Riker and Ordeshook, 1973; Amadae and Bueno de Mesquita, 1999).1

4Riker’s story fills different narratives, to which this article aims to contribute. The first is the history of game theory and, more generally, postwar mathematical economics, following the trail blazed by the works of Weintraub, Giocoli, and Leonard, among others (see Weintraub, 1992; 2002; Giocoli, 2003; Leonard, 2010). To these works must be added the reconstructions of the development of the postwar American Social Sciences and the notion of “cold-war” social sciences (see Amadae, 2003; Erickson, 2015; Erickson et al., 2015; Hauptmann, 1996). Finally, the development of American political science has been explored in many historical works. Indeed, the dramatic changes that occurred in the discipline in the postwar years (both in terms of its institutionalization and theoretical developments) framed Riker’s intellectual enterprise. Then, in the 1950s, a young generation of political scientists, like David Easton, Robert Dahl, and David Truman, among others, challenged the traditional approaches to political studies (history and law), advancing a plea for more empirical and quantitative analysis. Such a movement is known as the “behavioral revolution” in political sciences (Dahl, 1961; Somit and Tanenhaus, 1967; Adcock and Bevir, 2010; Adcock, 2009).

5Riker’s story fits all these narratives since he was a political scientist doing political theory when such “behavioral revolution” occurred. Riker indeed joined the “protest” against traditional political science, but not the revolution as a whole, focusing mainly on some tenets like the “plea” for objectivity in political theory. In doing so, he explicitly saw economics as a role model and adopted game theory. Therefore, this article also aims to contribute to the ongoing literature about the various attempts to extend the economics toolkit outside its traditional boundaries, closely following other works (see, for example, Medema, 2000; Medema, 2013; Fleury, 2010). We intend to show that Riker’s case was not a simple transfer of tools from one domain to another. The American political scientist indeed stressed those aspects of economic theory that fit his scientific, political science idea. However, he interpreted economics, especially its methodology, differently from what postwar mathematical economics was becoming.

6Riker’s use of game theory and formal analysis was strictly influenced by his being a political scientist working within the political scientist community. Then, whereas the development of game theory deeply affected the way postwar economists used to address theoretical problems, both in terms of mathematical sophistication and how they interpreted economic knowledge, Riker saw game theory differently. To him, this tool enhanced a strong predictive power, and his employment of it is justified on the basis of a robust positivistic attitude, which resembles Milton Friedman’s case for “positive economics” but also the “nomological-deductive” approach. However, it is well known that such positions were far from being the main force that fuelled economics’ radical postwar mathematization. This, in our eyes, represents a sort of “dilemma” that, as it will become apparent, Riker was not really able to solve. This work explores why Riker chose such a methodological point of view and how this affected his use of game theory or the immediate suitability of his model. In a nutshell, our thesis is that Riker presented to political scientists a relatively less sophisticated image of economics than what economics was becoming in the postwar years, and we try to advance some explanations for this.

7Section 1 and 2 describe Riker’s education and intellectual life until the late 1950s and how he became acquainted with game theory. Section 3 presents Riker’s main arguments in The Theory of Political Coalitions, focusing on his working through game theory to produce a suitable model of political coalition-building. Riker’s argument in this work was neither mathematical nor axiomatic. Thus, it is very different from the high theoretical game theory development in the 1950s (think of Princeton and RAND theorists). Consequently, it does not occupy a central place in the history of the development of game theory qua theory. However, it had an important role in how game theoretical ideas crossed domains different from economics. Section 4 discusses Riker’s relations with economic theory and outlines his methodological “dilemma.” Finally, Section 5 offers concluding remarks.

1. William H. Riker’s Education and Early Works

  • 2 One can derive information about Riker’s life and career from the brief biographical memoir written (...)
  • 3 E. Pendleton Herring (1903-2004) was an American political scientist, a generation younger than Mer (...)

8William Harrison Riker was born in Iowa in 1920 and grew up in Michigan and later in Indiana, where his father, in the years of the Great Depression, established a bookstore.2 He enrolled at DePauw University (IN), where he obtained a B.A. in Economics in 1942, and later spent some time during the war working for the RCA (Radio Corporation of America). Riker, in his remarks, attributed influence to these undergraduate studies in economics only for what concerns the “mindset” of economics and not for the specific training he received. Indeed, it is likely that the general undergraduate education in economics at the time, especially in a relatively small private provincial college like DePauw, was of low interest (and devoid of any theoretical inclination). After having completed his undergraduate studies, he decided to apply to graduate school in political science. Riker recollected that his set of possible choices comprised Harvard University, Columbia, and Chicago, namely, “[t]he three schools that were producing substantial numbers of political scientists at the time” (Riker, 1979, 36). Especially the latter was associated with Charles Merriam and the “Chicago School of Political Science,” which put much emphasis on empirical methods and quantitative analysis (on the “Chicago School”, see Heaney, 2006). Thus, his political science professor at DePauw, Harold Zink, advised him to apply to Chicago. However, at the time, Riker was influenced by the writings of E. Pendleton Herring, a professor at Harvard. Therefore, he decided to enroll there in 1945. Herring was a generation younger than Merriam but followed him in advocating scientific methods in social sciences and had a pivotal institutional role in developing the “Social Sciences Research Council,” which he chaired from 1948 to 1968 (Riker, 1979, 36 et ss).3

9Young Riker’s Harvard experience is extremely interesting to properly understanding the state of political science in the late 1940s and 1950s. In particular, it can be seen as a proxy of the problematic relationship between younger and innovative scholars within the unsatisfactory framework of a consolidated discipline. He arrived at Harvard before the period of intense methodological development and commitment to the quantitative method he would later define as “the ferment of the 1950s,” which coincided mainly with the “behavioral revolution” in political science and the development of new quantitative and qualitative analyses (Riker, 1997). At Harvard, in the 1940s, instead, the approach followed even by scholars more committed to the scientific method like Herring was mainly that of case studies, with a particular focus on public administration. Otherwise, the other important strand of research was the history of political ideas. Whereas Riker dismissed the earlier as “simply artistic investigations of events” (Riker, 1979, 39), the latter instead embodied what David Easton, at the time Riker’s fellow graduate student at Harvard, defined as the “historicist attitude in modern political theory,” equally opposed to empirical and theoretical analysis (Easton, 1951). In Riker’s own words, such a historicist attitude was defined as follows: “The idea was to have a clever interpretation of some event or a clever interpretation of some historical development and not to have a scientific approach to politics.” (Riker, 1979, 45) To his eyes, its main representative at Harvard was the famous German scholar Carl J. Friedrich, about whom he spent some harsh words in the interview with Shepsle (Riker, 1979, 41). In reality, in the pre-behavioral era, Friedrich was among the few scholars interested in setting empirical research within an original theoretical framework by establishing a theory of power. Consequently, he was pretty dismissive, as Riker was, of simplistic empirical analysis. But to Riker, Friedrich’s work, equally hostile toward any general description of political events, was without any usefulness in establishing a science of politics.

  • 4 The “Congress of Industrial Organization” was a former American trade union federation.

10Riker concluded his Ph.D. in 1947 with a fairly classical case study dissertation titled The CIO in Politics. 1936-1946 (under the supervision of Merle Fainsod; Fellman, 1947).4 In general, Graduate School experience did not satisfy him, and this mirrored the discipline’s scientific and intellectual state. On the one hand, there were people like Herring (to whom Riker felt personally close) who pursued interesting practical analysis but with totally wrong methodologies and devoid of theoretical exploration. On the other hand, people like Friedrich defended the case for a theoretical discipline, but at the expense of any practical purpose, at least to Riker. In such an intellectual environment, the “behavioral revolution” occurred in the late 1940s and early 1950s. It originated from the same intellectual concerns and dissatisfaction with the present state of political science Riker and other young scholars had. Take, for instance, the aforementioned Easton, whose work will be pivotal in this “behavioral revolution” (Adcock, 2009). He remarked, in an interview given for the “Political Science Oral History Program,” that “by the time I left Harvard, I just didn’t know what political science was all about.” (Interview with D. Easton in Baer, 1991, 199) These words are extraordinarily similar to those of Riker. Indeed, he stated that “people go out of Harvard without having any sense of doing anything in political science” (Riker, 1979, 48), and he “had no sense of what one did as a scholar in political science when [he] got through and finally [got a] Ph.D. [at] Harvard” (Riker, 1979, 44).

11The main tenets of the “behavioral revolution” entailed the emphasis on prediction and the explanation of political issues. These were based on observation and data collection, the development of interdisciplinary and “self-conscious criticism” about its methods and results. But also on pure research, leaving aside any normative aspiration to establish the “truth or falsity of values” like democracy, freedom, or equality, which are not amenable to scientific validation. Theoretical development occupied an important role in orienting and directing research (Somit and Tanenhaus, 1967). But this did not represent an explicit unified paradigm or set of theories. Instead, in the words of Robert Dahl, “those who were sometimes called ‘behavioralist’ … shared a mood: a mood of skepticism about the current intellectual attainments of political science, a mood of sympathy toward ‘scientific’ modes of investigation and analysis, a mood of optimism about the possibilities of improving the study of politics” (Dahl, 1961, 255). Up to conclude that “‘the behavioral approach’ might better be called the ‘behavioral mood’ or perhaps even the ‘scientific outlook’” (Dahl, 1961, 258). Besides, according to Riker, an important point was also occupied by reformist goals and practical interest in public affairs, which animated the young political scientists (Riker, 1997).

12Riker certainly shared such a mood but focused his attention more on the theoretical aspects rather than on the empirical analyses carried forward by behavioralists like Dahl or David Truman. Indeed, despite resting on more sophisticated methods than before, especially about statistical estimations (although far less advanced than incipient econometrics), the methodology of political theory was, to him, still grounded on flawed and unspecified ways of reasoning. These flaws became apparent to him after he published his textbook on the American political system, Democracy in the United States (Riker, 1953), primarily based on his teaching course in American politics at Lawrence College (WI), where he worked between 1949 and 1961 (Riker, 1979, 50). In his vivid account, working on this book led him to rethink the foundations of political science. In fact, after having published it, he started to realize that “it would be hard to say that any sentence in it was true” (Riker, 1979, 60); “I began to think that once you raise the question of what can you do to bring a particular moral position into some sort of effective institutional operation, why you also raise the question of whether or not institutions accomplish what they are intended to accomplish” (Riker, 1979, 2). Therefore, entailing an answer to these questions needed more than a normative stance and more than a plain description of how institutions work.

13In Riker’s mind, the issue at stake became that of ascertaining what political science is and if it does utter or not true sentences. Therefore, in his case, the strongest incentive to develop his intellectual agenda was the perceived need for a rigorous foundation of the methodological premises of the discipline. To pursue this ambitious aim, Riker started reading the philosophy of science and logic. But he soon realized that logic bore more on the validity of argument than its truth content. So, he paralleled these studies with more applied mathematical courses (Linear Algebra and Calculus) before discovering von Neumann’s and Morgenstern’s Theory of Games and Economic Behavior around the mid-1950s (Riker, 1979, 5 et ss).

2. The “Ferment of the 1950s”: Riker Meets Game Theory

14Riker recalled that “von Neumann’s book was the one that really turned me on because it seemed to me that there were some generalizations there that ... one could look at in nature and see if those generalizations turned out to be true.” (Riker, 1979, 5) Clearly, it was an intimidating book, especially for a political scientist with little math training. However, Riker felt confident to grasp the most important results from it, and, as we will show in the following section, he developed his theory of political coalitions entirely out of von Neumann and Morgenstern and not on other results of cooperative game theory.

15Riker quickly became “something of a publicist” for game theory in political science. For example, he insisted that the political theory panel at the “Midwest Conference of Political Scientists” at the University of Michigan, Ann Arbor (April 1958) was devoted to game theory, paralleling more traditional issues (Harry Davis to Riker, January 10, 1958). On that occasion, Riker presented a brief working paper that exposed some game theory principles for political analysis to fellow political scientists. (“Contribution of Game Theory to Political Theory”; Riker, 1958) He started by addressing some difficulties applying game theory in political science, commencing with political scientists’ lack of mathematical training. Nevertheless, he stated, the game-theoretical approach had much relevance to politics since

the category of zero-sum, two-person games is clearly a model for those political situations in which two persons are each trying to do the other in. ... The n-person game is clearly a model of the contemporary nation-state system of the free market of classical economy or of legislatures with undisciplined parties. (Riker, 1958, 2-3)

  • 5 Riker’s oversimplified model assumed two opposing coalitions and a neutral one. Therefore, there ar (...)

16In doing so, he stressed the normative features of the theory over the descriptive analyses usually outlined in political science. Riker concluded his brief exposition with a simple game-theoretical model of the “balance of power system.” A “balance of power system” in international relations assumes that to avoid the system’s collapse each member opposes anyone who gains a predominance position. Riker showed that game theory could carry this idea one step further. With three coalitions, two opposing and a neutral one, he looked for those situations where the neutral’s interest was to join the strongest coalition (so destroying the balance), and those where it was dominant be otherwise.5

  • 6 It must be noted that Nash, in his last contribution to game theory, advanced an attempt to establi (...)

17When Riker’s path crossed game theory in the second half of the 1950s, some scholars had made key refinements upon the original theory of von Neumann and Morgenstern so that this now was labeled as “cooperative game theory,” juxtaposed to the “non-cooperative” one. In a nutshell, cooperative game theory refers to the presence of coalitions where communication and, therefore, binding agreements are possible. On the other hand, non-cooperative theory refers to situations where players cannot communicate with others. Both these situations entail strategic and rational choice considerations, but the rules of the game and, therefore, the solutions are different. Princeton mathematician John Nash was the first to introduce this distinction. He, differently from what von Neumann and Morgenstern had done in their original 1944 work, treated a case where it is “assumed that each participant acts independently, without the collaboration of communication with any of the others” (viz. where coalitions are not permitted; Nash, [1950b] 2002). Nash famously defined such games as “Non-Cooperative Games.” The earlier games addressed in Theory of Games and Economic Behavior came, therefore, to be labeled as “Cooperative Games.”6

18In the cooperative case, the fundamental issue is that of choosing which coalition to join, given each player’s expectations regarding the payoffs, what he will obtain by selecting a coalition over another (through “side payments”), and finally, which partition of the game represents the solution to it. Besides, in this case, there are multiple notions of solutions, each with axiomatic and substantive properties that make them acceptable, both from a mathematical and rational point of view. To von Neumann and Morgenstern, for n-person zero-sum games, each coalition’s worth can be represented by a “Characteristic Function,” and what each coalition gives its members by a vector, defined as “imputation.” Due to their vectorial nature, each imputation can be related to another, using the notion of “dominance.” Then, a solution for a n-person game is offered by the set of all imputations that do not dominate each other and dominate all the imputations outside this set (this was called the “Stable Set”). However, this was not the only solution for such games. Other ideas came out, stressing one property or another of the definition of cooperative games (as the “Shapley Value,” discussed below).

  • 7 This brief volume contained the pages where von Neumann and Morgenstern discussed the meaning of th (...)
  • 8 Shapley was a Princeton Mathematics Ph.D. who worked at RAND during the 1960s and 1970s, providing (...)

19In 1954, Martin Shubik, a young economist who studied under Morgenstern at Princeton and was perhaps the only economist at that time deeply interested in game theory, edited a brief collection of essays exploring the theory of games in political behavior (Shubik, 1954; Shubik, 1992).7 The same year, Shubik, together with Lloyd Shapley, a Princeton and RAND mathematician,8 published in the leading journal of American political science, the American Political Science Review a short theoretical work addressing the everlasting issue of political power, using cooperative game theory (Shapley and Shubik, 1954).

20They defined power as the chance, represented by a “Power Index,” each committee member has of being critical to the success of a winning coalition (Shapley and Shubik, 1954, 787). The authors conceived their method as a first step to addressing such problems as designing the size and type of legislative bodies, protecting minority interests, and even finding a criterion for “fair representation.” Their analysis does not consider any sociological or political superstructure in a legislature; nevertheless, they argued, it could help set up norms or standards, “the departure from which will serve as a measure of, for example, political solidarity or regional or sociological factionalism in an assembly” (Shapley and Shubik, 1954, 791). This index represents the a priori chance for each committee member to be pivotal for a minimal winning coalition.

21Then, one can interpret Shapley and Shubik’s power index as a “technical definition of power” compared to the popular analysis of power, namely, the ownership and use of resources or the act of domination or influence of some individuals over others.

  • 9 This is the summary made by Riker in his 1959 paper. See below.
  • 10 As Shapley and Shubik (1954, 787-788) wrote: “Put in crude economic terms, the above implies that i (...)
  • 11 In simple terms, think of a group of individuals who must vote for some bill in a given order. As s (...)
  • 12 Unlike von Neumann and Morgenstern’s “Stable Set” and the “core,” which also applied to similar gam (...)

22In a formal, although not axiomatic way, their model can be summed in the ensuing terms:9 given a voting body of n-members and a rule to define victory in a vote—for instance simple majority rule, (n+1)/2 if n is odd and (n/2)+1 if n is even—members vote according to a sequence. Letting n! the total number of these sequences, and defining a minimal winning coalition, that is a coalition such that, if one member is subtracted, then it is not winning anymore, the member who transforms a coalition from losing to winning in a sequence is said to be a “pivot” (this means that the marginal value of the vote after (n/2)+1 is zero).10 Therefore, concerning each member i, the power index Pi is the ratio between the number of sequences in which i pivots and n! (where Σi=1...n Pi=1).11 Such a result is elaborated upon what is perhaps Shapley’s most famous contribution to game theory, viz. the value named after him, a general solution for n-person games, with transferable utility and binding agreements (Shapley, 1953).12

23In a late reminiscence, Riker attributed to Shapley and Shubik’s article a pivotal role in catalyzing his interest in game theory. Then, he summed up the importance of their result:

Most persons who have tried to analyze power have interpreted it as the ability of one person to make another person do something the other would not otherwise do. While I have deep reservations about this (and most other definitions of Power [Riker, 1962]), it is clear that Shapley’s definition is quite different. It involves not the ability to control persons but the ability to control outcomes through being the pivot or the marginal person between winning and losing coalitions: the last added member of a minimal winning coalition. (Riker, 1992, 212)

  • 13 Note, however, that in the original paper by Shapley and Shubik, no such strong maximization hypoth (...)

24Not surprisingly, the first article Riker devoted entirely to game theory was an attempt to assess Shapley and Shubik’s result empirically (Riker, 1959). In particular, he interpreted their result as the assumption that people seek to maximize their power. Therefore, their preference for joining a coalition over another is led by this “maximization principle.”13 However, as Riker pointed out, even if it could be demonstrated that each member raised his power by moving from one coalition to another, it could be impossible to prove that this was the leading motive behind his decision. Furthermore, Riker’s empirical test simply consisted of computing, through the roll-call of the French Legislative Assembly, how the power of each member who switched his side changed after his migration, and the final empirical assessment was uncertain at most.

25From Shapley and Shubik’s power index, a vast literature emerged that applied this and other similar indices to legislatures, committee decisions, or even to the analysis of fairness criterion (Straffin, 1994). However, when Riker made his ambitious attempt to provide a full-breadth game-theoretical analysis of political coalitions, he took from Shapley and Shubik only the notion of a “minimum winning coalition.” Instead, he rested on the original analysis of von Neumann and Morgenstern. Moreover, he explicitly rejected any definition of rationality in terms of “maximization of power.”

  • 14 The CASBS is still an active research center. One can consult a comprehensive list of fellows in de (...)

26A decisive step in Riker’s commitment to formal analysis was provided by the year (1960-1961) he spent as a fellow at the “Center for the advanced studies in behavioral sciences” (CASBS) at the University of Stanford. The Center was established in 1954, thanks to the funding of the Ford Foundation, and quickly became part of the set of non-academic institutions that shaped the “cold war rationality” (Amadae, 2003, 78-79; Erickson, 2015). The Center was well-funded and gave many opportunities for interdisciplinary research in social sciences, displaying, therefore, a less hawkish attitude toward game theory and formal analysis than, say RAND. Then, among the lists of fellows, we find political scientists, sociologists, economists, psychologists, historians, jurists, and philosophers.14 Furthermore, it filled exactly the research opportunities Riker was looking for. Indeed, as he wrote in a letter to Ralph W. Tyler, a renowned educator who was the CASBS’ first director, Riker aimed to develop “a new formal or mathematical political science” and “to attempt to formulate some mathematical statements about coalitions and to devise tests of the adequacy of these statements” (Riker to Tyler, June 22, 1959). It was at Stanford that Riker wrote a significant part of his book on political coalitions, but he also explored the other main strands of formal political theory, namely social choice and voting paradoxes, after the pivotal contributions made by Duncan Black, Anthony Downs, and especially Kenneth Arrow (who was a professor at Stanford, and a CASBS’ member; Black, 1958; Arrow, [1951] 1962; Riker, 1961).

27Despite the time spent at the CASBS, there are no clues that Riker was much in touch with the community of game theorists in the 1950s. In general, with very few exceptions, the intellectual communities of economists, political scientists, and game theorists remained disjoint. The game theorists’ community was made up, in the 1950s, of young mathematicians interested in the most abstract developments more than in practical employment. In places like RAND, the emphasis was allegedly put on the applied strand of game theory, e.g., its use in strategic and international political issues, but pure theoretical research was easily funded even there. In that community, not surprisingly, Riker was an outsider, lacking the necessary advanced mathematical capabilities needed to produce new mathematical theoretical developments. Furthermore, political scientists at RAND were anyway much interested in issues like nuclear deterrence or, in general, strategic analysis (the most notable case was that of Albert Wohlstetter, but also Thomas Schelling spent research time at RAND: Amadae, 2003). Riker’s focus on a well-defined issue, coalition formation in politics, and within a well-defined framework, namely “cooperative game theory,” may explain his distance from game theorists and, more generally, from those dealing with international politics.

28But the most crucial reason for his being an outsider was perhaps that Riker was advancing his theoretical agenda by advocating game theory. This agenda differed considerably from traditional approaches in political science as well as from the most recent “behavioral revolution.” Meanwhile, it was not easy to be integrated into the actual developments of game theory due to Riker’s mathematical difficulties.

29In the aforementioned interview with Shepsle, when asked if he ever sent any of his ideas to contemporary game theorists, Riker remembered only Duncan MacRae, whose response filled with detailed criticisms is not, unfortunately, among Riker’s papers stored at Rochester (Riker, 1979, 14). Another equally interesting proof of his being an outsider among the community of game theorists can be found in Oskar Morgenstern’s papers at Duke University. Riker completed The Theory of Political Coalitions in 1961 and sent the manuscript to Princeton University Press and Yale University Press. At Princeton, Morgenstern was extremely critical, rejecting its publication (Martin Shubik Papers, Box 8). Indeed, in a letter sent to Gordon Hubel (who was press editor at Princeton University Press), Morgenstern wrote: “The basic attempt is very laudable, and nobody doubts that Game Theory will influence Political Science vary considerably, but the execution leaves much to be desired.” (Morgenstern to Hubel, August 16, 1961) He continued: “Even the outline of Game Theory itself is full of misunderstandings and gaps. A reader not acquainted with Game Theory would not understand the exposition, and one already familiar with it would quickly spot the error” (ibid.). Morgenstern attributed the poor mathematical quality of Riker’s manuscript to his having worked by himself and advanced the suggestion to establish some cooperation with a real game theorist or spend some time obtaining a specific education in it. In fact, before writing his comment, he tried to detect who Riker was and what were his education, capabilities, and scientific research, but without obtaining any meaningful information. Finally, to remark on his point, he stated that “I am sure that anyone else who is at home in Game Theory and who would see this manuscript, perhaps given to him by some other publisher, would come to the same conclusion.” (Morgenstern to Hubel, August 16, 1961, Oskar Morgenstern Papers, Box 83)

  • 15 Riker never knew that his referee was Shubik, although he imagined it. See Riker (1979, 14).

30Despite Morgenstern’s harsh criticism and last remark, another refereeing was more supportive. Yale University Press contacted Martin Shubik at the end of June 1961 with the proposal of reading and making a referee (anonymously) of Riker’s manuscript (Marian Neal Ash to Shubik, June 30, 1961, Martin Shubik Papers, Box 8).15 For many aspects, the request made by Yale University Press was not surprising since Shubik, as seen, was one of the few people involved in elaborating n-person game theory. Furthermore, although he divided his research activities between RAND and his work as an applied economist for important corporations (especially IBM and General Electric), he was also associated with Yale University. Indeed in 1961, he was visiting there, and he would become a full professor in 1963, spending all his career in New Haven.

31Shubik began his report praising Riker’s manuscript: “This manuscript is well worth publishing. It will make a rather controversial book containing several imaginative ideas.” Moreover, “its worth depends upon an imaginative insight concerning the application of the methodology of game theory to the subject matter of political science.” (Shubik, 1961, 1) This, in his own eyes, can prevent the “unfair criticism” that political scientists and game theorists would have likely levied on technical grounds.

32This point is interesting and deserves attention: Shubik’s appraisal of Riker’s work and his defense of “unfair criticism” rests more upon methodological aspects, that is, the employment of game theory in political science, than on technical grounds. In fact, he judged Riker’s argument about minimum winning coalition “too verbal for one part of his audience and probably may not be sufficiently verbal for the other part.” Besides, it is not clear, Shubik stated, to which extent Riker’s resting upon previous literature (like the work of Raiffa and the work of Vickrey about coalitions) suited political theory.

33Focusing on the detailed comments on manuscripts, the only substantial analysis advanced by Shubik is about what seems to him too much emphasis on the zero-sum model. To his eyes, much of Riker’s analysis would also hold in a non-zero-sum game, mainly because the most crucial feature of his game-theoretic analysis is the indeterminate temporal length. In contrast, zero-sum is well-defined only for a small finite part of the game. Instead, the main feature is the opposition of interest, which is a prerogative of a zero-sum (and constant sum) game and in a “more or less strictly competitive non-constant sum game” (Shubik, 1961, 2). Other comments are less substantial, although still interesting, like contesting that “side payments” has an underlying reference to money, as stated by Riker (although Shubik admitted that this is a common misconception of game theory). Still related to this is the remark that “to include threats as a form of side payments leads to a rather poor modeling of human affairs.” Because “the result of a threat may be a rather low personal payoff to an individual. However, the threat itself is more properly a part of a strategy” (Shubik, 1961, 4).

34Shubik recommended Riker’s manuscript for publishing, even with only editing corrections. Interestingly, he also advanced some forecasts about this work’s reception: “The odds are that it will receive very mixed reviews, including several very favorable and several highly unfavorable comments. It is certainly not going to make any ‘best seller’ list. However, it should make a worthwile (sic) contribution to the development of political science.” (Shubik, 1961, 4)

  • 16 Except for that concerning the inclusion of threat as side-payment. In the published version of his (...)

35As stated above, Shubik’s name was not attached to the referee report. Besides, there is no sign of correspondence between Shubik and Riker before and even after the refereeing process. Moreover, given the vagueness of the comments and the fact that they were about to the manuscript version, unavailable in the archives, of Riker’s book, it is not easy to detect if they were effectively accepted by Riker.16 Notwithstanding, this report is interesting for many reasons. From the historian’s point of view, it represents a convincing appraisal of Riker’s work, made by one of the leading game theorists of his time. Shubik was perhaps the best choice to evaluate Riker’s work. As he repeatedly stated, his leading talent rested more on being an economic model builder than a mathematical economist (Shubik, 1992).

  • 17 A research program in which even Shubik himself was involved with. See Cogliano (2019).

36Then, maybe, some other author could have focused his attention on the poor mathematical nature of Riker’s work rather than, as Shubik did, on its general structure. As a matter of example, another reviewer could have pointed out the fact that coalition theory was being tentatively employed to obtain existence as well as stability results in general equilibrium theory.17 But probably, such criticism would have totally missed the point. Riker aimed not to offer a sophisticated mathematical theory of political coalitions or to elucidate their mathematical features. Instead, he wanted to provide new insights into political processes by modeling rational behavior following the methodological considerations explained in the first chapter of his work (see below). Although distant from Riker’s concerns (from a disciplinary point of view), Shubik understood this perfectly, as his referee report demonstrates. An issue which, instead, apparently was not caught by Morgenstern.

37Thus, whereas Princeton, the place where game theory was initially created and where there was a small but enthusiastic community of game theorists, rejected Riker’s manuscript, Yale instead accepted it, and The Theory of Political Coalitions was finally published in 1962.

3. Riker’s The Theory of Political Coalitions (1962)

38Riker’s The Theory of Political Coalitions represented the most significant accomplishment of the author’s intense commitment to game theory and formal analysis. He published other such general works only in the 1980s, although his focus shifted from game theory to social choice analysis, political theory, and American History (see, for example, Riker, 1982). This effort was an extraordinarily ambitious enterprise that aimed to construct, using an “existing general theory of coalitions (the theory of n-person games),” a theory of coalitions useful in studying politics and that rested on exact and verifiable assumptions (Riker, 1962, vii).

  • 18 The idea of the minimal winning size was not conceived originally by Riker but was instead develope (...)

39Riker was not a mathematician, and his work is not (“most emphatically not”, ibid.) a book about mathematics. This is apparent to the reader acquainted with game theory by his discussion concerning some extremely formal points. Such weaknesses notwithstanding, his attempt deserves much praise. His main thesis is that political actors will create coalitions just as large as they believe will ensure winning and no larger. This is the notion of “minimum winning coalitions,” namely that winning coalitions will be constrained in their size.18 This idea still occupies a central place in the formal study of political behavior and party formations, although the specificities of Riker’s inquiry were disputed on theoretical and empirical grounds (Butterworth, 1971; Riker, 1971; Shepsle, 1974; McKelvey, 1975). In the second half of his book, Riker slightly modified the n-person analysis of von Neumann and Morgenstern into a set partition of the voting members to describe the dynamics of coalition formations, that is, the strategy at the steps before a winning coalition is established. His theoretical ambitions in this part are even less fulfilled than in the first part, especially because the point to be addressed was far beyond the author’s technical capabilities. However, one could find some useful insights into the effective working of political systems even there.

  • 19 Riker had elaborated upon the first two elements in the philosophical papers written in the late 19 (...)

40The first chapter of the book, which the author later defined to Shepsle as “the most important part of the book” (Riker, 1979, 15), was devoted to presenting the assumptions of his model, as well as a general analysis of the role of modeling in political science. In these pages, Riker defended a positivistic attitude concerning social science through a mixture of (at least) three arguments: the necessity for social scientists of focusing only on phenomena whose size was easy to circumscribe; of providing an adequate notion of causal determinism; and finally of testing theories against facts in the real worlds, to enhance their predictive and explanatory power.19 The theory of games fits all three, since, in Riker’s view, it refers to well-defined events with clear relations among all the variables and entails both explanation and prediction.

  • 20 Note that in this situation, the difference between cooperative and non-cooperative games, vanishes (...)

41In the same pages, Riker also discussed the two fundamental assumptions of his model, namely, individual rationality and the zero-sum property. The latter refers to those situations that entail pure conflict. Von Neumann showed that for the case of 2-players only, the solution was determined by the “minimax theorem” (a result corresponding to the Nash Equilibrium for the same games).20

  • 21 James Buchanan and Gordon Tullock’s The Calculus of Consent was published in 1962 (Buchanan and Tul (...)

42Zero-sum also enters in the determination of the n-players coalition game since the value of each coalition, its “Characteristic Function,” is determined through a 2-person zero-sum game between each coalition and its opposite. However, not all political situations are of pure opposition. For instance, the most crucial feature of politics, as stated by James Buchanan and Gordon Tullock, requires that people are compelled to accept the decisions of the majorities, even if they are hostile to them. Therefore, it involves the need to balance between them.21 Nevertheless, Riker defended this assumption by noting that the zero-sum condition is present in many political situations, for instance, elections and voting, where the loser cannot receive what the winner gains. Besides, he also observed that even non-zero-sum situations could be perceived by the people involved as pure conflict. Then, he did not discard this assumption.

  • 22 In particular, Riker criticized rationality as presented in Luce and Raiffa’s work: to them, the th (...)

43The second fundamental assumption of the model was that of individual rationality. In particular, Riker criticized the “tautological” view adopted by economists, which purportedly does not describe behavior but only defines preferences.22 To him if any idea of rationality is helpful in modeling political behavior, one must adopt the “cruder and already somewhat discredited” idea of maximizing economic or political man. However, he rejected the idea of the maximization of power since it is difficult to define what power really meant (as seen in his empirical analysis of Shapley and Shubik’s work; Riker, 1959). He assumed instead that political rationality encompasses the preference for winning over losing. So then, a rational political man does not act according to his chance of gaining more power by passing from a coalition or a party to another (as presumed in the 1959 paper) but instead according to his chance of becoming a member of a winning coalition. This embodies the notion of political behavior that rules the nature of political coalitions. Indeed, in pursuing this aim, each member must face the fact that the value of the coalition is determined not by size but instead by its ability to remain winning, as long as it reduces its size to its minimum winning level.

44The bulk of Riker’s analysis is centered around the “size principle,” namely “the fundamental principle concerning the size of coalitions,” that goes as follows: “In n-person zero-sum game, where side-payments are permitted, where players are rational, and where they have perfect information, only minimum winning coalitions occur. (Riker, 1962, 32, italics in the text) A descriptive statement (or “sociological law”) is related to this principle: “In social situations similar to n-person, zero-sum games with side-payments, participants create coalitions just as large as they believe will ensure winning and no larger.” (Riker, 1962, 32-33)

  • 23 Both, in game-theoretical analysis, have a technical meaning. In particular, side payments are rela (...)

45As is apparent from the definition above, this principle requires rationality, side payments, and perfect information. All are standard assumptions in von Neumann and Morgenstern’s analysis. The role of side payments is that each player decides to join a coalition over another based on what he is offered in them. Perfect information instead rules out the role of uncertainty.23 In Riker’s model, side payments have great importance in his discussion of the strategical aspects of coalition-building, viz., the dynamical part of his analysis. Perfect information refers instead to each player knowing what moves the other players have made. This aspect is essential for what Riker defined as the “information effect,” which, according to him, represented the proper way to appraise the effects of the size principle in real-world politics (Riker, 1962, 77 et ss.; see below).

46As seen, Riker aimed to discuss political coalitions, namely coalitions involving winners and losers. Then, the framework of his analysis is cooperative and not competitive since it involves coalitions and, therefore, communication and agreements among players. Unfortunately, as he rightly noted, no unique solution exists for such games (contrary to the latter type, where a solution is a Nash Equilibrium). In his view, the cause is that too much emphasis has been put by game theorists on the properties of coalitions, like their existence, reasonableness, or fairness, overlooking instead the possibility of delimiting coalition structures directly. Since among the different solutions that followed von Neumann and Morgenstern’s, none appeared to him significantly preferable to the latter, neither in terms of empirical testing nor generality, Riker based his analysis directly on the original solution concept developed by the creators of game theory (von Neumann and Morgenstern, [1944] 2007).

  • 24 By coalition, in formal terms, it is intended the number of all the possible subsets of n, also com (...)

47The essential idea is that when the number of players is greater than 2 (naming N the set of all players), each coalition that forms in a game, from the coalition made up of a single player only to the coalition of the whole set of players, has a value which is defined by its “Characteristic Function,” v(S) (where S is a set of players,  N).24 This value is the solution of a 2-person zero-sum game between this coalition and its opposite, that is, v(S) = - v(S). Among the properties of each Characteristic Function, the most intuitive is perhaps its additivity; that is, the value of each coalition is greater than the sum of each component. Each coalition splits its value between its members in the following way: none receives less than he would receive by forming a coalition alone, and only the value of the coalition can be split, no more and no less. The vector of the values for each coalition member is called “imputation.” An imputation dominates another if all its components are greater than the other. Then, the solution of a n-person game is the set V of all imputations that do not dominate each other (inner stability) and dominate all the imputations outside the set (external stability).

  • 25 As seen, a minimum winning coalition is a coalition that is winning as long as it does not lose one (...)

48Riker focused only on those coalitions that are winning, i.e., that are larger than some size, arbitrarily ruled (for instance, m, where ≥ ½). In those cases, he tried to show that, other than the stability conditions entailed in the “Stable Set” solutions for n-person zero-sum game, a further principle was working, that is, the value of each winning coalition, v(S) (its Characteristic Function) reduced with the growth of its size. Put differently, a minimum winning coalition is worth more than a non-minimum winning coalition.25

49Riker restated von Neumann and Morgenstern’s original model, in a more straightforward and less mathematically sophisticated way, to describe in a statical way the coalitional structure of a political situation modeled as a n-person game. However, he also interpreted such a structure in terms of equilibrium and disequilibrium. Each v(S) can assume a range of values, which is a function of its size, and the size of the opponent blocking or losing coalition. Riker’s definition of equilibrium and disequilibrium directly reflects each agent’s strategy and rational decisions in the coalitions. In particular, he defined the notion of “equilibrium” in terms of each coalition’s realizability or not. Then:

  • 26 Unfortunately, Riker was not sufficiently precise about what the criterion of realizability refers (...)

[i]f there are some values of v(S) so unnecessarily disadvantageous for S as a whole that rational players reject S in favor of an immediately available alternative T, then these values of v(S) will be said to be in disequilibrium and S will be said to be unrealizable. Conversely, those values of v(S) which are not disadvantageous in comparison with an immediately available alternative will be said to be in equilibrium, and S will be said to be realizable. (Riker, 1962, 262, italics in the text)26

50He outlined three different types of winning coalitions:

  • those whose value decreases monotonically with the growth of their size;

  • those that gain by adding new members, at least until a certain point. After that point, the value decreases;

    • 27 Again, Riker’s analysis is quite involute. He adopted a notion in von Neumann and Morgenstern’s The (...)

    those whose values are indifferent to their size.27

51Intuitively, the first states that the value of the coalition decreases with the growth of its size. The second case relates instead to a coalition that gains by adding new members, at least until a certain point. Finally, there are coalitions whose values are indifferent to their size. So then, the puzzle is the following: if having reached a majority a coalition deems its own size disadvantageous and prefers to leave out some members, then this is not an equilibrium. Riker showed that, in the first type, the only equilibrium, that is, the only coalition that is realizable is represented by a minimum winning size. In the same way, in the second case, coalitions are realizable only until the peaked point is reached. Finally, the only equilibrium size in the third case is m, the arbitrarily chosen size (Riker, 1962, 245 et ss).

52Riker was looking to develop a theory that could be used to make predictions and to be tested against the reality of political facts through the formal structure of his assumptions. As he wrote: “whether or not the just-stated conclusion is of any scientific value depends on whether or not an analogous statement about real-world can be verified.” (Riker, 1962, 47) The “analogous statement” is the “size principle,” which states that in social situations similar to n-person zero-sum game, only coalitions no larger than the minimum size occur.

  • 28 The other two examples from American History are the rise of the Republican Party as a consequence (...)

53However, to assess the principle empirically, one has to face the problem of “perfect information.” Assuming that each member of the coalition can estimate its size subjectively, it could represent a possible getaway inside the model. But it would be clearly insufficient to fulfil Riker’s positivistic approach. He recognized the possibility of arranging laboratory experiments to simulate and test different types of games, but also that, lacking a specific methodology and rules, the results would be partial. Therefore, he looked for such empirical assessment in American History. In particular, if one could show that political leaders made strenuous efforts to reduce their oversized coalition in the direction of a minimum winning one, he could verify the size principle (Riker, 1962, 54). He picked up three examples from American History. Often an oversized coalition (for instance, a coalition of the whole that, since the assumptions regarding its Characteristic Function, is valued nil) was reduced by its leader through the expulsion of some of his members. This happened in the case of Andrew Jackson’s Democratic Party, which emerged from the fragmentation of Democratic-Republican Party (which Riker labeled only “Republican Party”), the only party that remained in the US after the disappearance of the Federalist Party as a consequence of the War of 1812.28 These pages make apparent that Riker was adopting an explicit “instrumentalist” position:

I do not suggest, of course, that these nineteenth-century statesmen appreciated this principle as a law of rational behavior. What I do insist, however, is that it describes their behavior, even though they probably perceived their problems thus: With our overwhelming majority, there are so many and so conflicting interests in the party that none can be satisfied. As long as two conflicting interests remain in the party, neither can be satisfied [which, I add, is why a grand coalition is valueless]. For the sake of action for the interest we approve, we shall therefore decide to satisfy one interest, and if others are offended, they may leave the coalition. (Riker, 1962, 65-66).

54In a similar spirit, he integrated the role of information in his model by outlining a relationship between the level of information of each player in a coalition and the size of the winning coalitions. Namely, the greater the degree of incompleteness of information, the larger the size of coalitions. This rule, which Riker named “the information effect,” could explain why minimal winning coalitions are often not found in the real world. But, also, why some elections in US history have been “critical.” The American political scientist V. O. Key developed the notion of “critical election” to define those elections where the voters’ involvement is high and new electoral groupings are created (Riker, 1962, 90 et ss). But, Riker stated, one could interpret this notion as a period where the amount of information in the system declined and the uncertainty grew about the size of the winning coalition.

55Riker also elaborated upon some statements from Anthony Downs’ economic analysis of democracy. According to the latter, in a 2-parties model, where voters want to maximize their utility and parties want to maximize their share of votes, it could be convenient for both parties to be as ambiguous as possible. However, this would contradict the assumptions about voters’ utility maximization because this makes it more difficult to vote rationally for each citizen, thereby encouraging voters to make their decision on some different basis from issues (viz, the candidates’ personality). This paradox represented a blow to any attempt to use rationality to define voters’ and parties’ behavior. However, Riker was convinced that his model offered a getaway from this situation. If parties seek to maximize the share of votes only up to the size needed to become a minimum winning coalition, therefore, it is not any more convenient for them to becloud their positions in any situation, but only about those issues that are of concern to voters about whom they have imperfect information. So the principle that parties and voters are rational (i.e., utility maximizers) is preserved.

56The “size principle” represented an ideal standard to which any reasonable attempt to form a coalition should conform. In this sense, although resting on von Neumann and Morgenstern’s solution for n-persons games, it was not a solution for such games but a “sociological principle.” In the second part of his work, Riker investigated how political leaders set forth coalition-building and reached a stable arrangement if any. This analysis aimed to fully exploit what the author later recalled as the main feature of game theory, namely the choice of strategies (Riker, 1992).

57In a nutshell, Riker discussed how coalitions are formed, maintain their structure, or add new members across a multi-stage game whose last stage represents the outcome of the process. For example, in voting, where a weighted majority is required, different coalitions are present (or “proto-coalitions” in Riker’s terminology). Then, the leader of each proto-coalition tries to add new members, if necessary, by offering side payments. If, in the final stage, the coalition structure is such that a minimum winning coalition occurs, then this represents an equilibrium outcome.

58Riker outlined his model as follows: assume a decision-making body, I, made up of n-members (i.e., a n-person zero-sum game with side payments). In this body, there are different roles, but each member can assume any role. Each member’s power (i.e., the weight) is assumed to vary. The decision rule is that a coalition with weight m, where m is greater than half the sum of the weight of each player, can act as a whole. The ZSC imposes a limit; no decision can be taken, so losers would prefer to resign from the body rather than acquiesce. In this model, coalition building begins when a leader that is a member of the decision-making body undertakes the task of forming a coalition on a particular issue. To this aim, the leader needs to attract followers among the other participants of the decision-making body. Given the focus on the dynamic process, Riker distinguished between coalitions and “proto-coalitions.” In brief, the first are end products of coalition-building and can be “winning,” “losing,” or “blocking.” Followers join instead in a “proto-coalition,” a subset of I when this has at least three subsets, and none has weight m. These proto-coalitions change their size due to moves made by each member of I, and each move has the effect of changing the body’s internal structure. Thus, in the first stage of such a game, there are n-single member coalitions. In the second stage, there are (n - 1)-single-member proto-coalitions, one 2-member proto-coalition, and so on, up to the last stage, where either a winning coalition or different blocking coalitions exist.

59Since any attempts to build a coalition generate opposition, the effect of the leader’s first step toward building a proto-coalition is that others follow him and try to build their coalitions. The growth of proto-coalitions depends on the leaders’ ability to attract followers by offering side payments (Riker, 1962, 122). These side payments can vary, but Riker listed some examples. These are payments in promises on particular policies, or subsequent decisions, up to the threat of reprisal. Besides, these side payments also have costs, which the coalition leader pays, and must consider (Riker, 1962, 109-120). Most importantly, Riker assumed that side payments were scarce and finite, subject to considerations regarding their economic value.

60The study of dynamic coalition building is important because it involves strategic considerations about the behavior of political actors and the equilibrium outcomes and, therefore, their inner stability. To discuss these features, Riker introduced a notion “in some respect stronger, and in some weaker” than von Neumann and Morgenstern’s set-valued solution because the latter did not specify if some coalition in the V-set was winning. He proposed the notion of a “uniquely preferable winning coalition,” which involves the specification of a determined winning coalition. A uniquely preferable winning coalition is a coalition that has a greater value than any other one possible and in which all the participants can satisfy their initial expectations. An “initial expectation” for a proto-coalition equals the best it can do in joining alternative non-minimal winning coalitions.

61From these considerations, any proto-coalition has some advantages (and disadvantages) in different stages of the game. An equilibrium solution is such that when a “uniquely preferred winning coalition” occurs, none of the other proto-coalitions can neither join it or form a new winning coalition. Since this entails the “size principle,” then an equilibrium corresponds to the presence of a minimum winning coalition.

62However, the most crucial problem with this kind of analysis is that the equilibrium in coalition-building cannot be maintained (i.e., it is not stable), but it seems to depend on the size and the relative strength of the minimum winning coalition (Riker, 1962, 147). The effects of this lacking of equilibrium for political analysis could be very serious: “equilibrium in society is a kind of stability despite the change. And to say that this model lacks equilibrium is to say that the social processes it purports to describe are so unstable that the political society itself is in fact unstable.” (Riker, 1962, 147-148) Therefore, the last three chapters of The Theory of Political Coalitions contained a purely verbal discussion about the components of this disequilibrium and its consequences.

63Once more, Riker rested on History to assess this theory. In particular, the event he tried to explain was the so-called “corrupt bargain of 1825,” when Andrew Jackson won a majority in the electoral college but lost the vote at the House in favor of John Quincy Adams, who became the sixth President of the United States (Riker, 1962, 149-159).

  • 29 The value of each coalition corresponds to the number of states where each candidate had the majori (...)

64Suppose this event is analyzed in terms of the dynamics of coalition building. In that case, one can assume that the four presidential candidates were leaders of four different “proto-coalition”: Jackson, Adams, William H. Crawford, and Henry Clay (who entered the election, but since there was a maximum of three candidates for a vote in the House, he was forced to transfer his votes.) The values of the proto-coalitions were the following: w(P) = 11 (Jackson), w(Q) = 7 (Adams), w(R)=3 (Crawford) and finally w(S) = 3 (Clay).29 Since Clay, Adams, and Crawford were hostile to Jackson, the latter’s proto-coalition was “strategically weak,” whereas they Q, R, S formed a “uniquely preferred winning coalition.” Jackson’s coalition shrinks, whereas Adams’ now became the preferred one. The new values were: Adams with 9 states, Jackson with 7, and Crawford and Clay with 4 each. To obtain a majority, Adams could ally with Crawford or Clay, but not with both, to maintain a minimal winning coalition. Eventually, an alliance between Clay and Adams occurred and was the dominant strategy from the latter’s point of view. Indeed, if Clay allied with Jackson (despite their ideological differences), Crawford would have allied with Adams, forming a minimal winning coalition. If Clay joined Crawford, now they had the same values as Jackson. Jackson and Clay-Crawford would have won the election, but the total value would have been split three ways over two. Given these strategic possibilities, Clay joined Adams, a majority was reached, and Adams was elected as the sixth president of the United States. Clay became his Secretary of State.

65Then, the historical argument again serves Riker to show the explaining power of his model and provide the basis for a new understanding of historical and contemporary political facts. Again, furthermore, Riker stressed the fact that his example did not show that Adams, Clay, or Jackson were employing game theory or rational choice, but that their behavior can be explained as if they did.

4. Political Science and Economic Modeling: Riker’s Unsolvable Dilemma?

66Rikers work was reviewed in the American Political Science Review and other social sciences journals (Fagen, 1963; Matthews, 1963; Hotz, 1962; Kaplan,1963; Flanagan, 1965). All the reviewers highlighted Riker’s methodological originality and the importance of his non-trivial generalizations about politics (although with some reservations about the notion of rationality). Yet, none stressed its formal features. Indeed, none of the reviewers was a real expert in game theory. As to economics, the book went completely unnoticed in economic journals.

67As Riker lamented in Shepsle’s interview, not many people had a sense of his work’s theoretical features (Riker, 1979, 24). Political scientists indeed focused only on some aspects of his model, especially the last three verbal chapters. Furthermore, as it is apparent from many reviews, Riker’s idea came to be framed and discussed mainly in international politics. Riker’s last chapter, where he tried to detect some considerations about the developing rivalry between the United States and the Soviet Union, caught the readers’ attention more than the formal characteristics of the model. Besides, Riker’s adoption of von Neumann and Morgenstern’s solution went mainly unnoticed by game theorists. Consequently, the importance of Riker’s work on political coalitions rests upon its being the first attempt to elaborate a model of political behavior explicitly based on a game-theoretical approach, even if this was far from reaching the levels of contemporary formal analyses in economics. Although Riker’s work did not offer anything new to the development of game theory, it still represented, in the light of what formal political theory became from the 1960s onwards, the first step of one of the most successful translations of theoretical ideas from one domain to another.

68A further episode can make apparent how economists and political scientists remained disjointed communities in those years. In a review of a comprehensive collection of essays about the different approaches to the study of politics, Riker complained about the lack of an economic approach (Riker, 1959). We believe that this complaint can be paralleled with the publication of a strictly formalized volume about the use of mathematics in the social sciences, with several highly mathematical essays about economics, management, and psychology, but no reference to political science (Arrow et al., 1959). Unsurprisingly this volume went unnoticed in political science journals. Indeed, only one reviewer (the future Nobelist Reinhard Selten) noticed, in Econometrica, the absence of an essay on political science (Selten, 1962).

69His theoretical shortcomings notwithstanding, The Theory of Political Coalitions, alongside other works, like that of Buchanan and Tullock, Anthony Downs and Duncan Black has marked the birth of a formal political theory (Ordeshook, 1986; Persson and Tabellini, 2002). Besides, among these authors, Riker was the only one who used game theory extensively and, overall, was a political scientist with a definite theoretical agenda.

70In the remnant part of this section, we discuss Riker’s use of economic theory concerning his agenda of transforming political theory and the development of postwar mathematical economics. In particular, Riker showed a sheer interest in some methodological issues, which can be confirmed by two philosophical papers, the first chapter of his work on political coalitions, and other works we will briefly address (Riker, 1957; Riker, 1958; Riker, 1962; Riker, 1977). In the meanwhile, however, he did not adopt deep methodological arguments. So, the main feature of his philosophy of science is represented by the robust faith in the idea of science as a positive discipline. In order to be a “genuine science,” a theory must display those elements that make it possible to explain the phenomena and predict their outcomes, eventually by discovering laws that relate different pieces of reality under a single theory. Riker’s approach is “nomological-deductive.” However, he paralleled such a view with a position entailing a more instrumentalist approach. Here lies what can be defined as “Riker’s dilemma.” He advocated the development of positive political science, resting heavily on formal assumptions, but the tools and the kind of analyses he was trying to adopt were far from being able to fulfil his aspirations.

71Following E. Roy Weintraub’s pivotal studies, historians of economics have interpreted the development of economics as a mathematical discipline in relation to the parallel development of mathematics as a formalist program. In this sense, postwar mathematical economics was not limited to employing math but mirrored the changes that occurred in this discipline, that is, “the changed standards for accepting proofs, changed ideas about rigor, and changed ideas about the nature of the mathematical enterprise” (Weintraub, 2002, 2). Similarly, Giocoli summed up the radical transformations in economics between the 1930s and the 1950s as two distinct visions of economics (Giocoli, 2003). The first is the idea of economics as a “system of forces,” which entails the idea that its main subject is the analysis of the processes generated by market and non-market forces, including—but not exclusively—the processes leading the system to an equilibrium. Economists paralleled this idea and replaced it with economics as a “system of relations.” According to the latter, “economics is a discipline whose main subject is the investigation of the existence and properties of economic equilibria in terms of the validation and mutual consistency of given formal conditions, but that has little if anything to say about the meaningfulness of these equilibria for the analysis of real economic systems.” (Giocoli, 2009, 24)

72Such a transformation was far from being accepted without resistance among economists and gave new fuel to the everlasting debates concerning the philosophy and methodology of economics. In particular, the spirit of new axiomatic economics challenged the most traditional views of the scientific enterprise as an explanation and, to a certain extent, a prediction of phenomena. For instance, it is pretty obvious that a mathematical model such as the “General Economic Equilibrium” model lacks both explanatory and predictive power. Indeed, it is explanatory only in the sense that a mathematical theorem explains something, and it is predictive in the same way. Then, as Pierluigi Barrotta rightly put it, Gerard Debreu’s statement, at the very beginning of his The Theory of Value, according to which his theory explains how the prices are determined from agents’ private ownership through markets and their role in an optimal state of an economy, could be seen as meaningless if one assumes that to explain something one has to find general laws relating different phenomena and their appearance (Barrotta and Raffaelli, 46; Debreu, 1959). This does not mean that economists are no longer trying to explain phenomena or advance their predictions about possible outcomes, but new languages and practices have been developed to fulfil this aim.

  • 30 “Instrumentalists claim that theories are best viewed as nothing more than instruments” (Caldwell, (...)

73In the case of economics, Milton Friedman presented a strictly positivistic view contending, among others, the development of the discipline as pure mathematical modeling. Friedman’s view is famous for advocating a radical instrumentalist approach and his seemingly unique belief that the realism of assumptions of theories does not matter.30 Still recognizing the extremely important place of “purely formal or tautological analyses” like those blazing the trail to postwar mathematical economics, given the extreme difficulty of testing substantive economic theories, Friedman, however, held that “economic theory must be more than a structure of tautologies if it is to be able to predict and not merely describe the consequences of action; if it is to be something different from disguised mathematics” (Friedman, 1954, 11-12). Since the most important feature of a theory is to predict something, mathematical modeling is not sufficient, and realism is not essential at all.

  • 31 Riker did not explicitly refer to Friedman in his work on political coalitions. But he did in the t (...)

74That Riker was seemingly close to such an idea of economics is apparent by how he defined the discipline in his work on political coalitions. To his readers, indeed, most likely political scientists, he defined economics as a “coherent theory and verified generalizations,” the product of “150 years of empirical investigation and refinement of theory” (Riker, 1962, 6). Furthermore, even his treatment of rationality and the attempts to assess his model empirically show an ostensibly “instrumentalist” influence (Riker, 1962).31

  • 32 Note, however, that Luce and Raiffa’s work was by far less mathematical than the vast part of contr (...)

75Starting with rationality, it is well-known that this notion went in the postwar years under a dramatic transformation in a mathematical sense. Giocoli defined this as the “consistency view” of rationality (Giocoli, 2003). In a nutshell, the core of this idea is that rationality does not describe behavior but only defines preferences in a purely tautological way, and the properties of the utility functions assume great importance in modeling individual rational behavior. However, Riker criticized this view, as represented by Duncan Luce and Howard Raiffa in their pivotal textbook Games and Decisions (Luce and Raiffa, 1957).32 In his eyes, if rationality is to help model political behavior, a simple mathematical tautology is not sufficient. On the contrary, as seen, one must adopt the more meaningful idea of a maximizing economic or political man. As a consequence, the problem of rational action and empirical validation should become: “how can the rationality condition be stated in such a way that it is more than a tautology but not subject to the criticisms implied in those experiments which show that the scale of individual utility is not the same as a scale of money” (Riker, 1962, 20). And the proper definition of rationality simply is:

Given social situations within certain kinds of decision-making institutions (of which parlor games, the market, elections, and warfare are notable examples) and in which exist two alternative courses of action with differing outcomes in money or power or success, some participants will choose the alternative leading to the larger payoff. Such choice is rational behavior and it will be accepted as definitive while the behavior of participants who do not so choose will not necessarily be so accepted. (Riker, 1962, 23, italics in the text).

76Furthermore, Riker also stated that not all behavior needs to be rational, but rational behavior is crucial for managing any economic or political institution. Thus, like the markets are controlled by those economic agents who adopt a maximizing behavior, the same holds for the working of political institutions that “select and reward with success behavior which is apparently motivated by the intention to maximize power” (Riker, 1962, 21).

77One can find even more strong references to a sort of instrumentalist position in the pages where Riker attempted to assess his “size principle” historically (Riker, 1962, 65-66). Then, as seen above, what matters to him is not that politicians closely employ game theory but that the model offers an accurate explanation of their behavior, thereby making possible a fuller understanding of it.

78Further details, although not developed systematically, concerning the nature and the scope he attributed to social sciences can be found in a review essay significantly titled The Future of a Science of Politics (Riker, 1977). Riker again rejected the particularistic study of political events, proper of the more traditional approaches of political studies, emphasizing instead a “positivistic view of science” whose central tenets are sets of scientific laws, i.e., “well-verified generalizations.” Besides, by scientific laws, Riker defined not only those discovered by observation but also theorems derived from axioms. He seemingly attributed the same scientific status and explanatory power to both:

Law and axioms thus reinforce each other. The necessity of the inference makes the law seem reasonable, and the empirical validity of the law makes the axioms seem true. Thus, with a theory, there is a much stronger reason than mere observation to accept a scientific law. (Riker, 1977, 15)

  • 33 Still notice that Riker’s praise of economic theory is at odds with some of the most recent results (...)

79Riker’s model for political theory is now explicitly price theory, that “satisfies, in structure and outcome, [his] notion of what a science is just as well as, perhaps, physics” (Riker, 1977, 22). This theory, he argues, states that price is determined by equalizing supply and demand in a competitive market.33 The law of demand can be derived by an empirical validation of how the quantity demanded varies when the prices rise or fall. This empirical validation can be extended to axiomatic theory, developing the theory of consumer choice. Despite the supply side of the price theory being less satisfying and intuitive from the empirical point of view than the demand side, economists generalized both demand and supply into a theory of competitive equilibrium. In Riker’s words:

[price theory] contains all the elements in our previous description of science. It starts with an empirical law, which is presumably universal when properly restricted. This law is then imbedded [sic] in a theory of choice. In turn, this initial theory is elegantly elaborated to produce a nonobvious and far from trivial inference about market clearing, which is in turn strongly supported by empirical evidence. (Riker, 1977, 21-22)

80If in this work, Riker’s position shows a “nomological-deductive” approach, assuming the importance, for the science, of discovering general laws in order to explain phenomena, in another paper, he returned to the issue of predictability (Riker, 1980). There, he explicitly stated that economics is a theory that admits predictions of an equilibrium. Furthermore, its prestige among other social sciences is due to the “actual occurrence of numerous predicted equilibria” (Riker, 1980, 434). Note that Riker generally refers to economic theory and not to a part of it (like, say, game theory).

81However, his close identification between equilibrium and predictions raises several problems for political theory. Riker linked the main advantage of equilibrium analysis to its ruling out interpretive and psychological motives behind people’s actions. As he wrote about one of the most important results of the theory of voting:

ideological extremists who vote eagerly for the party closest to themselves certainly intend to bring about extreme results; yet one social consequence, as McKelvey (1975) has elegantly shown, is that they drive parties to converge at the ideological center. No amount of sympathetic interpretation of individuals’ motives and actions can explain this unanticipated social result. ... Even when individuals accomplish exactly what they intend, social outcomes are not explained by interpreting motives. (Riker, 1977, 28)

82The failure to produce general results concerning the theory of voting (the most significant example in economics of such a general result being the General Economic Equilibrium), and, consequently, the flowering of many “impossibility results” (see especially those discovered by Richard McKelvey and Norman Schofield) scattered Riker’s faith in his positivistic idea of science linking equilibrium, individual rationality, and predictions so that he famously argued that not economics but

politics is the dismal science because we have learned from it that there are no fundamental equilibria to predict. In the absence of such equilibria, we cannot know much about the future at all, whether it is likely to be palatable or unpalatable, and in that sense, our future is subject to the tricks and accidents of the way in which questions are posed and alternatives are offered and eliminated. (Riker, 1980, 443, italics in the text)

83Therefore Riker, although not rejecting his positivistic program in toto, spent the remnant part of his career (he died in 1993) investigating further the institutional arrangements surrounding the persistence of disequilibrium and the occurrence of many, very fragile, temporary equilibria in choice settings.

  • 34 Ordeshook was among the first students to enroll in the Ph.D. Program in Rochester, established by (...)

84Not surprisingly, Riker’s strong arguments concerning the “dismal” character of political science called for a reply in the community of formal political scientists. Peter Ordeshook did one, and his response makes apparent the gap between Riker’s view and that of other advocates of formal modeling more in touch with economic analysis.34

85Ordeshook claimed that Riker attributed too much significance to the idea of equilibrium as stability and, therefore, to the idea that price theory itself referred to market stability. As it turned out, “the presumed stability of markets is an abstract fiction that most economists recognize as a a theoretical impossibility” (Ordeshook, 1980, 447, italics in the text). It was something existing in the formal model but not necessarily in reality. The same holds for the theory’s predictive power: abstract descriptions of markets might predict how a change in the general settings of the model affected prices and consumption but could not anticipate these changes. For instance, in a market with one seller and two buyers, the value of the coalition of buyers is zero. The core (i.e., the set of all undominated imputations) comprises only those imputations that attribute value to the seller and nothing to the buyers. Namely, the single seller is a monopolist and will extract all the added value from any exchange. Nonetheless, it could be reasonable to assume that buyers could form a cartel and negotiate as a team, and a new equilibrium would arise. For example, this now becomes a bargaining problem, where the monopolist tries to obtain a distribution as advantageous as possible on the Pareto frontier. However, the core now consists of all the points in the Pareto frontier, and therefore, the existence of equilibria is not a sufficient condition for predicting outcomes (Ordeshook, 1980, 448).

86Ordeshook’s central point is thus that equilibria are elements of the formal model and therefore display features like existence, uniqueness, and stability but do not necessarily entail predictive power. This argument does not exhaust the question of the impossibility of collective choices but instead points to new ways of analyzing the problem. In particular, he called for political scientists’ genuine contribution to developing new formal models and not only to employ notions and ideas taken away from economics.

87Looking at the differences between Riker’s argument and Ordeshook’s allows a final appraisal of how Riker used game theory and economic theory and how this differed from postwar neoclassical economics and other attempts to extend economic reasoning across domains different from economics. Returning to Giocoli’s distinction between “economics as a system of forces” and “economics as a system of relations,” Riker’s analysis looks closer to the former vision. Indeed, to him, equilibrium is not an analytical framework within which formal analysis can be conducted (and neither the solution of a game) but instead a relationship of forces. Take, for instance, how, in his work on political coalitions, Riker defined this notion: “[T]he notion of equilibrium is that of a relationship of forces arranged so that the deviation from some point of balance results in a (possibly automatic) correction back to balance.” (Riker, 1962, 147) Only in this way, equilibrium can be related to prediction. Besides, this can also explain why he was so concerned with the issue of disequilibrium. Indeed, in a “system of forces” framework, disequilibrium, and equilibrium have the same importance. Since it is clear that reality, especially social reality, hardly shows anything similar to “physical” equilibrium, disequilibrium sometimes has a stronger appeal to the researcher. On the contrary, in a purely axiomatic model and within the notion of equilibrium widely employed in game theory (that is, Nash Equilibrium), equilibrium is simply the necessary outcome of the model, i.e., the solution of a problem modeled like a mathematical problem. Naturally, then, the main issue in such models is the existence or non-existence of equilibrium itself (and, possibly, its multiplicity).

88The point is that in economics, game theory was conceived within the “system of relations” framework. This simple historical fact shows how the entry of game theory into political science differed substantially from the way it entered economics. It also makes it apparent how the task Riker tried to accomplish, especially in his analysis of political coalitions, was arduous to achieve: not only because Riker lacked the advanced game-theoretic skills that could have made his research more mathematically robust, but also because he considered game theory from a viewpoint that was too different from his actual development in mathematics and, later, in economics.

89Finally, some hypotheses can be advanced for explaining Riker’s resting on the old idea of “economics as a system of forces.” Riker was an outsider among the community of game theorists and economists as well, so the most immediate hypothesis is that he simply lacked adequate knowledge of economics to fully assess its most recent developments. True as it could be, such an explanation is not sufficient. A suitable answer lies, in our view, in the fact that Riker was trying to make sense of the idea of political theory based on rational choice for political scientists, an audience much different from economists. In this sense, one could explain, for instance, his rejection of a preferences-based tautological argument regarding rationality (Riker, 1962).

  • 35 Besides, Riker implicitly adopted a preference-based idea of rationality when using the V-solution (...)

90He preferred a more meaningful definition over a purely mathematical approach because the earlier’s meaning could be easily grasped by an audience not comfortable with mathematical sophistication. But this raises, as seen, the problem of the wedge between what the theory can do and Riker’s positivistic aspirations. Then, the refusal of the preference-based approach pushed him toward a significantly weaker argument to defend rational choice, namely that, even if not all agents are rational, the most important agents are (a summation argument). In doing so, the author seems to discard what the rationality assumption in economics is, viz., one way to constrain the beliefs and desires people are allowed to have in order to make their actions explainable. However, he did not offer a valid alternative to explain individuals’ actions and properly model them. Indeed, restraining the set of individuals assumed to be rational does not preclude the fact that modeling rational behavior requires strong assumptions about people’s beliefs, preferences, and formal structure.35

91Compare Riker’s idea with von Neumann’s theory characterizing rational behavior with prudence. Indeed, in his 1928 paper and his 1944 work, rational behavior is represented by the “security payoff” given by the minimax strategy. Namely, a player does not need to know what his opponent’s plan will be in reality, but if he plays the minimax strategy, he will maximize his expected payoff in the worst possible case. (von Neumann, 1928; Giocoli, 2003b) This idea solves the paradox of perfect knowledge discussed in the 1930s by authors like Morgenstern and Friedrich von Hayek, albeit in different forms (Morgenstern, 1935; Hayek, 1937; see also Giocoli, 2003). Like von Neumann, Riker focuses only on one feature of human behavior: the preference for winning outcomes. Avoiding a too narrow idea of rationality (i.e., that “individuals’ scales of utility ... are isomorphic with the scale of some objective measure such as money or even power”), he expected that “rationality as winning” could establish the foundation of a theory of political coalitions based on von Neumann and Morgenstern’s formal analysis. If one interprets Riker’s argument that way, it could be possible to understand why he chose it. Nevertheless, there is no contradiction between a formal argument and an idea of rationality that encapsulates concrete human behavior features. Von Neumann’s solution was criticized for equalizing rationality and prudence. However, it was not this aspect that undermined its acceptance, but the mathematical difficulty in proving a similar result for those situations (non-cooperative and cooperative) different from 2-person zero-sum game (a problem that the newborn idea of Nash Equilibrium overcame).

92To conclude, one could explain Riker as resting on an old idea of economic analysis as a “system of forces” that, attractive as it might be, was increasingly being displaced in the very area of economic analysis that he had selected as his theoretical reference (i.e., game theory) by new ideas concerning axiomatization through a view of economics as a “system of relations.” An area, it should be added, that until very recently has always been the most distant from the possibility of empirical validation. This, in a nutshell, was Riker’s unsolvable dilemma.

Conclusion

93This article showed how game theory entered political science and what was the role of William H. Riker.

94I focused on how Riker’s analysis differed from economics and formal game theory, primarily for what concerns the structure of the argument and the different scope pursued. I showed that Riker’s relationship with economics and game theory was, in a certain sense, fuzzy. He referred to economics as a role model, but his idea of economic theory was distant from that of economists at his time. His treatment of rationality lacks the generality for establishing a full-breadth theory and, indeed, will be discarded when “Positive Political Theory” aligns itself with economics. Besides, he understood what was missing in game theory but was an outcast in the community of game theorists.

95Riker certainly had a limited influence on the development of game theory qua theory. Instead, emphasizing the consistency of his theory with the explanation of real-world (or even historical) political phenomena served better his task of showing how functional game theory could be in political analysis. To this aim, more than a mathematical sophistication that few political scientists were barely able to grasp, he showed how political behavior was inherently game-theoretical and, therefore how fertile game theory was for allowing “political science to rise above the level of wisdom literature and indeed to join economics and psychology in the creation of a genuine science of human behavior” (Riker, 1962, viii).

96With the passing of the years, the difference between formal political science and economic theory narrowed, up to the point that important contributions were also published in economic journals like Econometrica or The Journal of Economic Theory. This process paralleled and was the effect of establishing a community of scholars entirely devoted to the formal analysis of political issues. At the same time, it opened a new stream of methodological issues, namely the attempts to reconcile positive aspirations with the ambition to develop a genuinely mathematical analysis (Austen-Smith and Banks, 1999). In the end, this was Riker’s most significant legacy. Such a story, which starts with Riker’s creation of the Political Science Graduate Program at Rochester University, is the necessary complement to this article.

I want to acknowledge Professor Giocoli, who supervised my Ph.D. dissertation; Professor Lapidus and Arena, who read a previous version of this work at the 2021 ESHET Summer School in Paris, providing useful insights; Catherine Herfeld, who similarly read a previous version of this work; and the participants to the STOREP Conference (2020), ESHET (2021) and HES (2021), who read and commented the previous versions of this article. Finally, special thanks to all the professors, the staff, and the fellows at the Center for the History of Political Economy at Duke, with which I had a lot of valuable exchanges in the eight months I spent there. I also want to acknowledge the staff of the Rare Collection at Rubinstein Library for having assisted my research, and finally, the Staff at the Rochester University Library.

Haut de page

Bibliographie

Archives

Davis, Harry 1958. Letter to William H. Riker, January 10, 1958. In William H. Riker Papers, David M. Rubenstein Rare Book and Manuscript Library, Duke University, Box 18, Folder 2.

McKelvey, Richard D. and Richard D. Smith. 1975. A Comment on The Debate Over Rikers “Size Principle”. Mimeographed. In William H. Riker Papers, Carnegie Mellon University, Box 19.

Morgenstern, Oskar. 1961. Letter to Gordon Hubel, August 16, 1961. In Oskar Morgenstern Papers. David M. Rubenstein Rare Book and Manuscript Library, Duke University, Box 83.

Riker, William H. 1958b. Contributions of Game Theory to Political Theory. Mimeo. In William H. Riker Papers. David M. Rubenstein Rare Book and Manuscript Library, Duke University, Box 18, Folder 2.

Riker, William H. 1959. Letter to Ralph W. Tyler, June 22, 1959. In William H. Riker Papers. David M. Rubenstein Rare Book and Manuscript Library, Duke University, Box 10, Folder 1.

Riker, William H. and Kenneth Shepsle. 1979. Interview to William Harrison Riker by Kenneth Shepsle. In William H. Riker Papers. David M. Rubenstein Rare Book and Manuscript Library, Duke University, Box 85.

Shubik, Martin. 1961. Referees report on The Theory of Political Coalitions by William H. Riker. In Martin Shubik Papers. David M. Rubenstein Rare Book and Manuscript Library, Duke University. Box 8, MSP.

Bibliography

Adcock, Robert. 2009. Interpreting Behavioralism. In Robert Adcock, Mark Bevir, and Shannon C. Stimson (eds), Modern Political Science: Anglo-American Exchanges since 1880. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 180-208.

Adcock, Robert and Mark Bevir. 2010. Political Science. In: Roger Backhouse and Philippe Fontaine (eds), The History of the Social Sciences since 1945. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 71-101.

Amadae, Sonja M. 2003. Rationalizing Capitalist Democracy: The Cold War Origins of Rational Choice Liberalism. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Amadae, Sonja M. and Bruce Bueno de Mesquita. 1999. The Rochester School: The Origins of Positive Political Theory. Annual Review of Political Science, 2(1): 269-295.

Arrow, Kenneth J. [1951] 1962. Social Choice and Individual Values. New York: John Wiley & Sons.

Arrow, Kenneth J., Carlin Samuel, and Patrick Suppes (eds). 1959. Mathematical Methods in the Social Sciences. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

Austen-Smith, David. 1999. Positive Political Theory. Volume I. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.

Baer, Michael A., Malcolm E. Jewell, and Lee Sigelman. 1991. Political Science in America: Oral Histories of a Discipline. Lexington: The University Press of Kentucky.

Barrotta, Pierluigi and Tiziano Raffaelli. 1998. Epistemologia ed Economia. Torin: Utet.

Black, Duncan. 1958. The Theory of Committees and Elections. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Buchanan, James M. and Gordon Tullock. 1962. The Calculus of Consent: Logical Foundations of Constitutional Democracy. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan.

Bueno de Mesquita, Bruce and Kenneth Shepsle. 2001. William Harrison Riker 1920-1993. A Biographical Memoir. National Academy of Sciences. Biographical Memoirs, 79.

Butterworth, Robert L. 1971. A Research Note on the Size of Winning Coalitions. American Political Science Review, 65(3): 741-748.

Caldwell, Bruce. [1981] 1994. Beyond Positivism. Economic Methodology in the Twentieth Century. New York and London: Routledge.

Cogliano, Jonathan. 2019. An Account of “The Core” in Economic Theory. Center for the History of Political Economy at Duke University Working Paper Series, 2019-17.

Dahl, Robert A. 1961. The Behavioral Approach in Political Science: Epitaph for a Monument to a Successful Protest. American Political Science Review, 55(4): 763-772.

Damiani, Gianluca. Forthcoming. Setting the Stage for Disciplinary Transformations. History of Political Economy, 56(3): 393-416.

Debreu, Gerard. 1959. Theory of Value. An Axiomatic Analysis of Economic Equilibrium. New Haven: Yale University Press.

Downs, Anthony. 1957. An Economic Theory of Democracy. New York: Harper & Row.

Easton, David. 1951. The Decline of Modern Political Theory. The Journal of Politics, 13(1): 36-58.

Erickson, Paul. 2015. The World the Game Theorists Made. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Erickson, Paul, Judy L. Klein, Lorraine Daston, Rebecca Lemov, Thomas Sturm, and Michael D. Gordin. 2015. How Reason Almost Lost Its Mind: The Strange Career of Cold War Rationality. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Fagen, Richard R. 1963. Review to The Theory of Political Coalitions. American Political Science Review, 57(2): 446-447.

Fellman, David. 1947. Doctoral Dissertations in Political Science: In Preparation at American Universities. American Political Science Review, 41(4): 754-770.

Flanigan, William H. 1965. Review to The Theory of Political Coalitions. Administrative Science Quarterly, 9(4): 454-456.

Fleury, Jean-Baptiste. 2010. Drawing New Lines: Economists and Other Social Scientists on Society in the 1960s. History of Political Economy, 42(Suppl.): 315-342.

Friedman, Milton. 1954. Essays in Positive Economics. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

Giocoli, Nicola. 2003a. Fixing the Point: The Contribution of Early Game Theory to the Tool-Box of Modern Economics. Journal of Economic Methodology, 10(1): 1-39.

Giocoli, Nicola. 2003b. Modeling Rational Agents: From Interwar Economics to Early Modern Game Theory. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar Publishing.

Giocoli, Nicola. 2009. Mathematics as the Role Model for Neoclassical Economics. In Richard Arena, Sheila Dow, and Matthias Klaes (eds), Open Economics: Economics in Relation to Other Disciplines. London: Routledge, 145-165.

Hands, D. Wade. 2012. What a Difference a Sum (∑) Makes: Success and Failure in the Rationalization of Demand. Journal of the History of Economic Thought, 34(3): 379-396.

Hauptmann, Emily. 1996. Putting Choice before Democracy: A Critique of Rational Choice Theory. New York: State University of New York Press.

von Hayek, Friedrich A. 1937. Economics and Knowledge. Economica, 4(13): 33-54.

Heaney, Michael T. and John Mark Hansen. 2006. Building the Chicago School. American Political Science Review, 100(4): 589-596.

Herring, Pendleton. 1947. The Social Sciences in Modern Society. Items, 1(1): 5.

Hotz, Alfred J. 1963. Review to The Theory of Political Coalitions. Midwest Journal of Political Science, 7(3): 295-297.

Kaplan, Morton A. 1957. Systems and Process in International Politics. New York: John Wiley & Sons.

Kaplan, Morton A. 1963. [Review on] The Theory of Political Coalitions. The Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, 347: 137-138.

Leonard, Robert. 2010. Von Neumann, Morgenstern, and the Creation of Game Theory: From Chess to Social Science, 1900-1960. Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press.

Luce, Duncan R. and Howard Raiffa. 1957. Games and Decisions: Introduction and Critical Survey. New York: John Wiley and Sons.

Matthews, Donald R. 1963. Review to The Theory of Political Coalitions. The Journal of Politics, 25(3): 578-580.

Medema, Steven G. 2000. “Related Disciplines”: The Professionalization of Public Choice Analysis. History of Political Economy, 32(Suppl.): 289-324.

Medema, Steven G. 2013. Creating a Paradox: Self-Interest, Civic Duty, and the Evolution of the Theory of Rational Voter in the Formative Era of Public Choice Analysis. Œconomia. History, Philosophy, Methodology, 3(1): 61-86.

Morgenstern, Oskar. 1976. Perfect Foresight and Economic Equilibrium. In: Andrew Schotter (ed.), Selected Economic Writings of Oskar Morgenstern. New York: New York University Press, 69-83.

Nash, John F. [1950] 2002a. The Bargaining Problem. In Harold W. Kuhn and Sylvia Nasar (eds), The Essential John Nash. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 37-48.

Nash, John F. [1953] 2002b. Two-Person Cooperative Games. In: Harold W. Kuhn and Sylvia Nasar (eds), The Essential John Nash. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 99-116.

von Neumann, John. 1928. Zur Theorie der Gesellschaftsspiele. Mathematische Annalen, 100(1): 295-300.

von Neumann, John von and Oskar Morgenstern. [1944] 2007. Theory of Games and Economic Behavior. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

Ordeshook, Peter C. 1980. Political Disequilibrium and Scientific Inquiry: A Comment on William Rikers “Implications from the Disequilibrium of Majority Ruler for the Study of Institutions”. American Political Science Review, 74(2): 447-450.

Ordeshook, Peter C. 1986. Game Theory and Political Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Persson, Torsten and Guido Tabellini. 2002. Political Economics: Explaining Economic Policy. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

Riker, William H. 1953. Democracy in the United States. New York: Macmillan.

Riker, William H. 1957. Events and Situations. The Journal of Philosophy, 54(3): 57-70.

Riker, William H. 1958a. Causes of Events. The Journal of Philosophy, 55(7): 281-291.

Riker, William H. 1959a. A Test of the Adequacy of the Power Index. Behavioral Science, 4(2): 120-131.

Riker, William H. 1959b. Review to Approaches to the Study of Politics. Midwest Journal of Political Science, 3(2): 207-210.

Riker, William H. 1961. Voting and the Summation of Preferences: An Interpretive Bibliographical Review of Selected Developments during the Last Decade. American Political Science Review, 55(4): 900-911.

Riker, William H. 1962a. The Calculus of Consent by James M. Buchanan and Gordon Tullock. Midwest Journal of Political Science, 6(2): 408-411.

Riker, William H. 1962b. The Theory of Political Coalitions. New Haven: Yale University Press.

Riker, William H. 1971. Comment on Butterworth “A Research Note on the Size of Winning Coalitions”. American Political Science Review, 65(3): 745-747.

Riker, William H. 1977. The Future of a Science of Politics. American Behavioral Scientist, 21(1): 11-38.

Riker, William H. 1980. Implications from the Disequilibrium of Majority Ruler for the Study of Institutions. American Political Science Review, 74(2): 432-446.

Riker, William H. 1982. Liberalism against Populism: A Confrontation between the Theory of Democracy and the Theory of Social Choice. San Francisco: Freemand and Company.

Riker, William H. 1992. The Entry of Game Theory into Political Science. In E. Roy Weintraub (ed.), Toward A History of Game Theory. Durham: Duke University Press; 207-223.

Riker, William H. 1997. The Ferment of the 1950s and the Development of Rational Choice Theory. In Kristen R. Monroe (ed.), Contemporary Empirical Political Theory. Berkeley: University of California Press, 191-201.

Riker, William H. and Peter C. Ordeshook. 1973. An Introduction to Positive Political Theory. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hal.

Roth, Alvin E. 1988. Introduction to the Shapley Value. In Alvin Roth (ed.), The Shapley Value. Essays in Honor of Lloyd S. Shapley. Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press, 1-27.

Schelling, Thomas C. [1961] 1980. The Strategy of Conflict. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

Selten, Reinhardt. 1962. Review to: Mathematical Methods in the Social Sciences by Kenneth J. Arrow, Samuel Karlin and Patrick Suppes. Econometrica, 30(3): 605-606.

Shapley, Lloyd S. 1953. A Value for n-Person Games. In Harold W. Kuhn and Albert Tucker (eds), Contributions to the Theory of Games. Princeton: Princeton University Press, vol. 2, 307-317.

Shapley, Lloyd S. and Martin Shubik. 1954. A Method for Evaluating the Distribution of Power in A Committee System. American Political Science Review, 48(3): 787-792.

Shepsle, Kenneth A. 1974. On the Size of Winning Coalitions. American Political Science Review, 68(2): 505-518.

Shubik, Martin. 1954. Readings in Game Theory and Political Behavior. Volume 9. London: Doubleday.

Shubik, Martin. 1992. Game Theory at Princeton, 1949-1955: A Personal Reminiscence. In E. Roy Weintraub (ed.), Toward A History of Game Theory. Durham: Duke University Press, 152-164.

Simon, Herbert. 1945. Review to The Theory of Games and Economic Behavior. The American Journal of Sociology, 50(6): 558-560.

Somit, Albert and Joseph Tanenhaus. 1967. The Development of Political Science: From Burgess to Behavioralism. Boston: Allyn and Bacon.

Straffin, Philip D. 1994. Power and Stability in Politics. In Robert J. Aumann and Sergiu Hart (eds), Handbook of Game Theory with Economic Application. Amsterdam: Elsevier Science Publishers, 1127-1151.

Taylor, Michael. 1971. Mathematical Political Theory. British Journal of Political Science, 1(3): 339-382.

Weintraub, E. Roy (ed.). 1992. Toward A History of Game Theory. Durham: Duke University Press.

Weintraub, E. Roy. 2002. How Economics Became A Mathematical Science. Durham: Duke University Press.

Haut de page

Notes

1 Positive Political Theory” was the name adopted by Riker yet in the 1950s. It will later become the standard label to define this subfield of political science. Riker’s approach has also been labeled sometimes as the “rational choice approach” in political science due to the emphasis put on methodological individualism and rationality. Besides, an important aspect of this story that is not discussed here is Riker’s role as an “intellectual entrepreneur” within the academic community of political scientists. Indeed, he did not just advance a methodological as well as theoretical agenda but was tireless in building up a group of scholars who shared his view. This came mainly from Riker’s role in chairing the department of political science at the University of Rochester from 1962 to 1977, and especially in establishing a Ph.D. program, to which such scholars like Peter C. Ordeshook, Kenneth Shepsle, Richard D. McKelvey, John Aldrich, among others, joined, namely some of the most important political scientists which employed formal theory in their works (see Damiani, forthcoming).

2 One can derive information about Riker’s life and career from the brief biographical memoir written by two scholars connected to him, Kenneth Shepsle and Bruce Bueno de Mesquita. The former obtained a Ph.D. in Political Science at Rochester in 1970 and was among the first Riker’s graduate students. Bueno de Mesquita instead did not attend Rochester Graduate School, but he arrived as a professor in 1972 and was very close to Riker. They wrote this memoir for the biographical series of the National Academy of Science, to which Riker belonged since 1975 (Bueno de Mesquita and Shepsle, 2001). It offers exciting accounts of Riker’s personality and family life and his role as teacher and mentor, but, given the nature of the series, the general tone is sometimes acquiescent and celebratory. In addition, Riker himself offered some different historical accounts of intellectual development (Riker, 1992; Riker, 1997). There, he aimed to present a general reconstruction of his academic experience, especially concerning applying game theory in political science. Hence, his narrative is often generic and not precise, at least from a historiographical point of view. The most interesting source for reconstructing Riker’s life is certainly the long and detailed interview Riker gave to Shepsle in 1979 as part of the “Political Science Oral History Program.” This program started in the late 1970s to preserve the experiences of major figures in the development of American political science to the benefit of future historians and practitioners of the discipline (Riker, 1979). This interview (consisting of no less than 150 typed pages) spanned from graduate and undergraduate education reminiscences to theoretical and methodological issues.

3 E. Pendleton Herring (1903-2004) was an American political scientist, a generation younger than Merriam but followed him in advocating scientific methods in social sciences. Besides, he also was strongly involved in the institutionalization of the discipline in the postwar, chairing the “Social Sciences Research Council” from 1948 to 1968. Dahl, in particular, considered the “Social Science Research Council” one of the “six specific, interrelated, quite powerful stimuli” that backed the development of the “behavioral approach” in political science (Herring, 1947, 763 et ss; Dahl, 1961).

4 The “Congress of Industrial Organization” was a former American trade union federation.

5 Riker’s oversimplified model assumed two opposing coalitions and a neutral one. Therefore, there are two possible outcomes: the neutral coalition joins the weakest opposing coalition, and the balance of power is maintained; otherwise, the neutral coalition merges with the strongest one, and the balance system is broken. By using Shapley and Shubik’s power index, Riker computed the power of each coalition. Then he showed how much each coalition should offer to the neutral one to ally with it. Besides, Riker also attempted to display the best strategy for the neutral coalition. However, his model is far from being detailed and general, and even his employment of the power indices is a very special case with arbitrary values.

6 It must be noted that Nash, in his last contribution to game theory, advanced an attempt to establish the “non-cooperative” foundations of “cooperative games,” presenting a model of bargaining where the determination of the bargaining solution was obtained through a non-cooperative threat game (Nash, [1950b] 2002). An entire research program, the so-called “Nash Program,” was derived, especially from the 1980s onward, after John Harsanyi and Reinhardt Selten invented some pivotal extensions and refinements of Nash Equilibrium.

7 This brief volume contained the pages where von Neumann and Morgenstern discussed the meaning of the notion of solution verbally; some reviews of Theory of Games and Economic Behavior; some research application of game theory to military problems (“The Colonel Blotto’s game”), and finally, although not, strictly speaking, game-theoretical analyses, the first pages of Arrow’s work on social choice, where he presented voting as a problem of collective choice, and Black’s 1950 paper about the “unity between economics and political science.”

8 Shapley was a Princeton Mathematics Ph.D. who worked at RAND during the 1960s and 1970s, providing critical applications of cooperative game theory and non-cooperative as well. He was awarded the Nobel Prize in Economics in 2012. For biographical information: https://www.nobelprize.org/prizes/economic-sciences/2012/shapley/facts/ [retrieved 02/03/2024].

9 This is the summary made by Riker in his 1959 paper. See below.

10 As Shapley and Shubik (1954, 787-788) wrote: “Put in crude economic terms, the above implies that if votes of senators were for sale, it might be worthwhile buying forty-nine of them, but the market value of the fiftieth (to the same customer) would be zero.” Note that in 1954 the U.S. Senate comprised 97 members.

11 In simple terms, think of a group of individuals who must vote for some bill in a given order. As soon as a majority is reached, the bill is passed, and the last member who voted is given credit. If the order of voting is chosen randomly, one can compute the frequency with which a member belongs to a group of voters, and the frequency of a member is pivotal. Then an index can be construed, which measures the number of times that the action of the individual changes the state of affairs. If this formal model is applied to a committee chairman’s tie-breaking function, in an odd committee, he is pivotal as often as an ordinary member; in an even committee, he is never pivotal. Then, for instance, applied to the case of the US Senate in the 1950s, the power index of the US vice-president was equal to 1/97 × (96+1).

12 Unlike von Neumann and Morgenstern’s “Stable Set” and the “core,” which also applied to similar games, the Shapley Value is not based on stability considerations. Instead, it entails the players’ “reasonable expectation of reward,” based on an a priori evaluation of the entire game. Namely, the value added to every coalition by a player is multiplied by the a priori probability that the coalition will form. The players’ Shapley values constitute a unique payoff vector as the game’s solution (Roth, 1988; Taylor, 1971). As Riker and Ordeshook stated: “The V-solution is inferred from the characteristic function in answer to the question: how might players in each coalition be expected to divide its value? On the other hand, the Shapley value is inferred from the characteristic function in answer to the question: how much might players expect to win, given various possibilities of coalitions?” (Riker and Ordeshook, 1973, 163)

13 Note, however, that in the original paper by Shapley and Shubik, no such strong maximization hypothesis was advanced.

14 The CASBS is still an active research center. One can consult a comprehensive list of fellows in decades on its site. Among them, eight future Nobel Prizes in Economics.

15 Riker never knew that his referee was Shubik, although he imagined it. See Riker (1979, 14).

16 Except for that concerning the inclusion of threat as side-payment. In the published version of his work, “the threat of reprisal” is still maintained among the various kinds of side payments in politics (Riker, 1962, 109-110).

17 A research program in which even Shubik himself was involved with. See Cogliano (2019).

18 The idea of the minimal winning size was not conceived originally by Riker but was instead developed by Shapley and Shubik. However, Riker employed this notion in a way different from them. He did not compute each player’s value to play a given game (in a nutshell, Shapley’s original idea) or the power that each member of an assembly entailed. Instead, the purpose of this notion was to constrain the coalition structure of a game, explore its equilibrium and stability, and offer a way to test these results.

19 Riker had elaborated upon the first two elements in the philosophical papers written in the late 1950s, where he, in his words, “squabbled over methodology” (Riker, 1957; Riker, 1958).

20 Note that in this situation, the difference between cooperative and non-cooperative games, vanishes, since it is not possible, according to the zero-sum condition, to form a coalition. Instead, in the case of 2-person games without opposition of interests, the solution is the so-called “Nash’s bargaining solution” (Nash, 1950b).

21 James Buchanan and Gordon Tullock’s The Calculus of Consent was published in 1962 (Buchanan and Tullock, 1962). Riker had written a very favorable review in the same year, praising their theory. Furthermore, he eventually joined the Public Choice Society after it was established (Riker, 1962b).

22 In particular, Riker criticized rationality as presented in Luce and Raiffa’s work: to them, the theoretical issue to be solved does not entail demonstrating that real men want to maximize money, power, or something else. Instead, it is sufficient to represent the preferences’ structure properly and, therefore, examine them empirically. Then Riker summed up their definition of rationality as follows: Given a social situation in which exist two alternative courses of action leading to different outcomes and assuming that participants can order these outcomes on a subjective scale of preference, each participant will choose the alternative leading to the more preferred outcome.(Riker, 1962, 18-19, italics in the text)

23 Both, in game-theoretical analysis, have a technical meaning. In particular, side payments are related to the notion of “transferable utility” among players. The first refers to the existence of a common medium that the players can exchange. If this is linear with the increment of the player’s payoff, then it is said that utility is transferable.

24 By coalition, in formal terms, it is intended the number of all the possible subsets of n, also comprising the empty set and the set of all players. This number equals 2n.

25 As seen, a minimum winning coalition is a coalition that is winning as long as it does not lose one of its members. For example, under simple majority rule, with two parties, a party with 51 members is a minimal winning coalition. If the winning party has 70 members, it is a winning coalition, but not a minimum winning one.

26 Unfortunately, Riker was not sufficiently precise about what the criterion of realizability refers to. For instance, it could be obvious to interpret it as a sort of “domination” criterion for each member of the coalition (recall that “domination” can be represented as if x > y for all x1, … xn, then x dominates. However, this analysis is not outlined in the appropriate formal terms.

27 Again, Riker’s analysis is quite involute. He adopted a notion in von Neumann and Morgenstern’s Theory of Games and Economic Behavior: the range of admissible values for each Characteristic Function. Then, among these values, in the space of “winning coalitions” Characteristic Function, he identified three types: those with a negative slope (type 1), those with a positive slope in part (type 2), and finally, those with zero slopes.

28 The other two examples from American History are the rise of the Republican Party as a consequence of the destruction of the Whig Party in the 1850s and the fragmentation of the Democratic Party in different Blocking Coalitions; the end of the Reconstruction, when the Republican Party, again a grand coalition de-facto divided in different coalitions, at state and local levels (Riker, 1962, 59-65).

29 The value of each coalition corresponds to the number of states where each candidate had the majority. In the House, each state had one vote, which was decided by a plurality of its representatives.

30 “Instrumentalists claim that theories are best viewed as nothing more than instruments” (Caldwell, [1981] 1994, 178). In this sense, such an approach is contrasted with realism, whereas the latter claim that theories should make real references. Note that Friedman did not explicitly characterize his position as “instrumentalist.” Lawrence Boland did it.

31 Riker did not explicitly refer to Friedman in his work on political coalitions. But he did in the textbook he wrote about the “Positive Political Theory” that he wrote with Peter C. Ordeshook (Riker and Ordeshook, 1973, 30), where this position is made explicit.

32 Note, however, that Luce and Raiffa’s work was by far less mathematical than the vast part of contributions to rational choice theory. Furthermore, still presenting the axiomatic idea of rationality, following especially von Neumann and Morgenstern’s treatment of “expected utility,” they were also concerned with the attempts to assess it empirically.

33 Still notice that Riker’s praise of economic theory is at odds with some of the most recent results of general equilibrium theory of the time, like the Mantel-Sonneschein-Debreu Theorem, which states that almost any function can be an excess demand function, thus making extremely hard to generate the appropriate conditions for stability of Walrasian equilibria (Hands, 2012).

34 Ordeshook was among the first students to enroll in the Ph.D. Program in Rochester, established by Riker in the 1960s and focused on formal theory and game theory. Ordeshook had co-authored, with Riker, the first textbook devoted to Positive Political Theory, in 1973, besides having offered pivotal contributions to voting theory and political game theory (Riker and Ordeshook, 1973).

35 Besides, Riker implicitly adopted a preference-based idea of rationality when using the V-solution of von Neumann and Morgenstern. Indeed, the fundamental properties in the notion of “imputation,” on which the two authors built upon their V-solution and Riker extensively discussed (although not in mathematical terms), encapsulated the notion of individual and collective rationality in preference terms (Luce and Raiffa, 1957, 192-193).

Haut de page

Pour citer cet article

Référence papier

Gianluca Damiani, « Looking for a “Genuine Science of Politics.” William H. Riker and the Game Theoretical Turn in Political Science »Œconomia, 14-2 | 2024, 149-193.

Référence électronique

Gianluca Damiani, « Looking for a “Genuine Science of Politics.” William H. Riker and the Game Theoretical Turn in Political Science »Œconomia [En ligne], 14-2 | 2024, mis en ligne le 01 juin 2024, consulté le 06 décembre 2024. URL : http://0-journals-openedition-org.catalogue.libraries.london.ac.uk/oeconomia/17069 ; DOI : https://0-doi-org.catalogue.libraries.london.ac.uk/10.4000/120il

Haut de page

Auteur

Gianluca Damiani

Ph.D. Student, University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill, gdamiani@unc.edu

Haut de page

Droits d’auteur

CC-BY-NC-ND-4.0

Le texte seul est utilisable sous licence CC BY-NC-ND 4.0. Les autres éléments (illustrations, fichiers annexes importés) sont « Tous droits réservés », sauf mention contraire.

Haut de page
Rechercher dans OpenEdition Search

Vous allez être redirigé vers OpenEdition Search