Bibliographie
Primary sources
Bentham, Jeremy, UCL collection of Bentham Manuscripts, boxes i–clxxvi.
Bentham, Jeremy, Defence of Usury; shewing the impolicy of the present legal restraints on the terms of pecuniary bargains, London, Payne, 1786
Bentham, Jeremy, The Works of Jeremy Bentham, now first collected; under the superintendence of his Executor, John Bowring, 11 vols., Edinburgh, Tait, 1838–43
Bentham, Jeremy: The Theory of Legislation, ed. C.K. Ogden, London, Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1931
Bentham, Jeremy, A Comment on the Commentaries and A Fragment on Government, eds. J.H. Burns and H.L.A. Hart, London, Athlone, 1977
Bentham, Jeremy, Constitutional Code, vol. I, ed. F. Rosen and J.H. Burns, Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1983
Bentham, Jeremy, Deontology Together with A Table of the Springs of Action, and the Article on Utilitarianism, ed. A. Goldworth, Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1983
Bentham, Jeremy, Chrestomathia, eds. M.J. Smith and W.H. Burston, Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1983
Bentham, Jeremy,: An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation, eds. J.H. Burns and H.L.A. Hart, Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1996
Bentham, Jeremy,: De l’ontologie et autres textes sur les fictions, ed. P. Schofield, trans. J-P. Cléro and C. Laval, Paris, Seuil, 1997
Bentham, Jeremy, Legislator of the World, eds. P. Schofield and J. Harris, Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1998
Bentham, Jeremy, Writings on the Poor Laws II, ed. M. Quinn, Oxford, Clarendon Press, 2010
Foucault, Michel, ‘Politics and the Study of Discourse’, in The Foucault Effect: Studies in Governmentality, eds. G. Burchell, C. Gordon, and P. Miller, Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 1991
Foucault, Michel, Essential Works of Foucault 1954-1984, vol i. Ethics, ed. P. Rabinow, London, Penguin, 2000
Foucault, Michel, Essential Works of Foucault, 1954-84, vol. iii. Power, ed. J.D. Faubion, New York, New Press, 2000
Foucault, Michel, Madness and Civilization: A History of Madness in the Age of Reason, New York, Random House, 2001
Foucault, Michel, The Order of Things: An Archaeology of the Human Sciences, London and New York, Routledge, 2002
Foucault, Michel, ‘Society Must be Defended’: Lectures at the Collège de France, 1975-76, eds. M. Bertani and A. Fontana, London, Penguin, 2003
Foucault, Michel, Security, Territory, Population: Lectures at the Collège de France, 1977-78, ed. M. Senellart, London & New York, Palgrave, Macmillan, 2009
Foucault, Michel, The Birth of Biopolitics: Lectures at the Collège de France, 1978-79, ed. M. Senellart, London & New York, Palgrave, Macmillan, 2008
Secondary Sources
Ben-Dor, Oren, Constitutional Limits and the Public Sphere: A Critical Study of Bentham’s Constitutionalism, Oxford, Hart, 2000
Burchell, G., Gordon, C., and Miller P., eds., The Foucault Effect: Studies in Governmentality, Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 1991
Burns, James H., ‘Nature and Natural Authority in Bentham’, Utilitas v (1993), 209-20
Danaher, G., Schirato, T. and Webb, J., Understanding Foucault, London, Sage, 2000
Dickens, Charles, Hard Times, London, Penguin, 1995
Engelmann, Stephen: Imagining Interest in Political Thought: Origins of Economic Rationality, Durham and London, Duke University Press, 2003
Laval, Christian, ‘From Discipline and Punish to The Birth of Biopolitics ’, in Beyond Foucault: New Perspectives on Bentham’s Panopticon, ed. A. Brunon-Ernst, London, Ashgate (forthcoming)
Semple, Janet E.‘Foucault and Bentham: A Defence of Panopticism’, Utilitas iv. (1992), 105-20
Haut de page
Notes
Semple, J.E., ‘Foucault and Bentham: A Defence of Panopticism’, Utilitas iv. (1992), 105-20.
‘Foucault and Bentham’, 118.
Essential Works of Foucault, 1954-84, vol. iii. Power (henceforth Power), ed. J.D. Faubion, New York, New Press, 2000, p. 240.
The words of Thomas Gradgrind, in Dickens, C., Hard Times, London, Penguin, 1995 (first published in Household Words, nos. 210–18, 1 April–5 August, 1854).
Foucault, M., The Order of Things: An Archaeology of the Human Sciences, London and New York, Routledge, 2002, p. 82.
Bentham, J., Chrestomathia, eds. M.J. Smith and W.H. Burston, Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1983 (CW), facing p. 179.
A Comment on the Commentaries and A Fragment on Government, eds. J.H. Burns and H.L.A. Hart, London, Athlone, 1977 (CW), p. 393.
‘Logic’, UCL collection of Bentham Manuscripts (Henceforth UC) ci. 183, in The Works of Jeremy Bentham, now first collected; under the superintendence of his Executor, John Bowring, 11 vols., Edinbrugh, Tait, 1838–43, (henceforth Bowring) viii. 238.
‘Truth and Power’ in Power, p. 131
‘Truth and Juridical Forms’ in Power, p. 32.
‘Logic’, UC cii. 349 (Bowring, viii. 309)
See Foucault, M., Madness and Civilization: A History of Madness in the Age of Reason, New Yor, Random House, 2001.
‘Society Must be Defended’: Lectures at the Collège de France, 1975-76, eds. M. Bertani and A. Fontana, London, Penguin, 2003, p. 9.
‘Universal Grammar, Appendix’, UC ci. 412 (Bowring, viii. 280). For the definition of interest, see ‘Of Ontology’, UC cii. 42, published in De l’ontologie et autres textes sur les fictions, ed. P. Schofield, trans. J-P. Clero and C. Laval, Paris, Seuil, 1997, p. 98 (Bowring, viii. 203): ‘Desire of pleasure and of exemption from pain, in one word interest, being in some shape or other the source of every thought as well as the cause of every action’.
The Birth of Biopolitics: Lectures at the Collège de France, 1978-79, ed. M. Senellart, London & New York, Palgrave Macmillian, 2008, p. 272.
The Birth of Biopolitics, p. 46.
See The Order of Things, p. 363.
Foucault, M., ‘Politics and the Study of Discourse’, in The Foucault Effect: Studies in Governmentality, eds. G. Burchell, C. Gordon, and P. Miller, Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 1991, p. 69.
« Elements of Critical Jurisprudence », UC lxx. 22
Ibid.
Ibid.
The Order of Things, p. 59; and compare Bentham, ‘Logic’, BL Add. MS. 33,550, fol. 8: ‘a principle by which the precision, clearness and incontestableness of mathematical calculation is introduced for the first time into the field of morals—a field to which, in its own nature, it is applicable with a propriety no less incontestable ... than to that of physics, including its most elevated quarter, the field of mathematics.’
An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation, eds. J.H. Burns and H.L.A. Hart, Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1996 (CW), (henceforth IPML), pp. 38-41.
‘Elements of Critical Jurisprudence’, UC lxx 22-3.
Ibid, UC lxx 23.
Ibid..
‘Universal Grammar’, UC ci. 407 (Bowring, viii. 279).
‘Universal Grammar’, UC cii. 460 (Bowring, viii. 330).
Ibid.
‘Elements of Critical Jurisprudence’, UC lxx. 23.
‘Of Ontology’, UC cii. 71, De l’ontologie, p. 146(Bowring viii. 210).
‘Elements of Critical Jurisprudence’, UC lxx. 23.
Ibid.
Ibid.
‘Of Ontology’, UC cii. 71, De l’ontologie, p. 146 (Bowring viii. 209).
‘Of Ontolgy’, UC cii. 71, De l’ontologie, p. 146 (Bowring viii. 210).
‘Logic’, UC cii. 203.
‘Universal Grammar’, UC cii. 456 (Bowring viii. 329).
‘Universal Grammar’, UC cii. 463.
‘Of Ontology’, UC cii. 75, De l’ontologie, p. 154 (Bowring viii. 211).
See, for instance, Writings on the Poor Laws II, ed. M. Quinn, Oxford, 2010 (CW), 186 n.: ‘Subjection, subjection not liberty, let it be remembered, is the natural, and for year on year, the universal state of man.’ For a very helpful general discussion, see Burns, J.H., ‘Nature and Natural Authority in Bentham’, Utilitas v (1993), 209-20.
The Order of Things, p. 344.
‘Logic’, UC ci. 390 (Bowring viii. 277).
See in general, ‘A Table of the Springs of Action’, in Deontology Together with A Table of the Springs of Action, and the Article on Utilitarianism, ed. A. Goldworth, Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1983 (CW), pp. 79-115.
Defence of Usury; shewing the impolicy of the present legal restraints on the terms of pecuniary bargains, London, Payne, 1786, p. 7 (Bowring, iii. 3). See also Bentham’s discussion of the stigmatization of homosexual sex with the epithet ‘unnatural’ in The Theory of Legislation, ed. C.K. Ogden, London, 1931, pp. 478-9.
See respectively S. Engelmann, Imagining Interest in Political Thought: Origins of Economic Rationality, Durham and London, Duke University Press, 2003, and O. Ben Dor, Constitutional Limits and the Public Sphere: A Critical Study of Bentham’s Constitutionalism, Oxford, Hart, 2000.
‘Of Indirect Means of Preventing Crimes’, in ‘Principles of Penal Law’, Bowring, i. 534.
‘Polemics, Politics and Problematizations’, in Essential Works of Foucault 1954-1984, vol i. Ethics, ed. P. Rabinow, London, 2000 (henceforth Ethics), p. 118.
‘Questions of Method’, in Power, p. 225.
‘Introduction’, in Ethics, p. xix.
I am grateful to Gianfranco Pellegrino for his insightful comments on this issue.
This interpretation of Foucault is widespread in the English speaking literature, amongst both critics and admirers, at least in regard to the knowledge contained in the human sciences: see, for instance, Danaher, G., Schirato, T. and Webb, J., Understanding Foucault, London, Sage, 2000, p. 131: ‘We cannot know the truth about ourselves, because their is no truth to know, simply a series of processes that make up the self.’ However, as Jean Pierre Clero notes in his article in this journal, Foucault himself came as near as makes no difference to denying it explicitly: see, for instance, ‘The Ethics of the Concern for the Self as a Practice of Freedom’, in Ethics, p.296: ‘But when I talk about power relations and games of truth, I am absolutely not saying that games of truth are just concealed power relations—that would be a horrible exaggeration.’
IPML,p. 75.
‘La philosophie analytique de pouvoir’, in Dits et écrits, iii. p. 540 (cited in Sellenart, M., ‘Course Context’, in Security, Territory, Population, Lectures at the Collège de France, 1977-78, ed. M. Senellart, London and New York, Palgrave Macmillan, 2009, p. 374).
Laval, C., ‘From Discipline and Punish to The Birth of Biopolitics ’, in Beyond Foucault: New Perspectives on Bentham’s Panopticon , ed. A. Brunon-Ernst, London, Ashgate (forthcoming).
‘The Ethics of the Concern for Self as a Practice of Freedom’, Ethics, p. 298. See also ‘The Risks of Security’, in Power, p. 372; ‘The Subject and Power’, in ibid. pp. 326-47.
‘Foucault and Bentham’, 119.
‘Logic’, UC cii. 204 (Bowring viii. 300-1 n.). See also ‘Universal Grammar’, UC cii. 460 (Bowring viii. 330 n.): ‘From these speculative observations, practical inferences of no small importance might be deduced. 1. Avoid dogmaticalness. 2. Still more avoid intolerance. In both cases never cease to bear in mind how slippery and hollow the ground on which your opinion, and consequently the utmost value of any expression which you can give to it, rests.’
‘Logic’, UC ci. 153 (Bowring, viii. 233).
‘Preparatory Principles Inserenda’ , UC lxix. 69.
Security, Territory, Population, p. 353.
See Security, Territory, Population, pp. 72-3.
The Birth of Biopolitics, p. 40. In relation to this development, Foucault refers explicitly to Bentham’s distinction between sponte acta, non-agenda and agenda at ibid. p. 24 n.
The Birth of Biopolitics, p. 63.
See The Birth of Biopolitics, pp. 39-43
The Birth of Biopolitics, p. 64.
The Birth of Biopolitics, p. 273.
Despite his anti-essentialism, there is a sense in which ‘interest’ is a fundamental concept for Foucault himself, and for the original genealogist of morals, Nietzsche. Thus, in rejecting the idea that there is any straightforward reproduction of sensation in the knowledge to which it gives rise, both argue that interest, in the shape of ‘an interplay of instincts, impulses, desires, fear, will to appropriation’, compromises all claims to objectivity: ‘Interest is thus posited radically prior to the knowledge that it subordinates as a mere instrument’ (Foucault, ‘The Will to Knowledge’, in Ethics, p. 14).
See ‘First Lines of a proposed Code of Law for any Nation Compleat and Rationalized’, in Legislator of the World, eds. P. Schofield and J. Harris, Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1998, pp. 194-208.
‘Course Context’, in Security, Territory, Population, pp. 387-8.
‘Polemics, Politics and Probelmatizations’, in Ethics, p. 117. Similar enumerations appear in ‘Preface to the History of Sexuality, Volume Two’, and ‘On the Genealogy of Ethics’, in Ethics, pp. 204, 262 respectively.
‘The Ethics of concern for the self as a practice of freedom’, in Ethics, p. 300.
‘On the Government of the Living’, in Ethics, p. 81.
‘The Ethics of concern for the self as a practice of freedom’, in Ethics, p. 300.
The Birth of Biopolitics, p. 40.
‘Interview with Michel Foucault’, in Power, p. 295.
‘Interview with Actes’, in Power, p. 399.
The Order of Things, p. 358.
‘Sex, Power, and the Politics of Identity’, in Ethics, p. 167.
The Birth of Biopolitics, p. 192.
‘Interview with Michel Foucault’, in Power, p. 294.
Security, Territory, Population, p. 3.
‘What is Enlightenment?’ in Ethics, p. 316.
‘Interview with Michel Foucault’, in Power, p. 275.
‘Sexuality and Solitude’ in Ethics, p. 177.
‘The Ethics of concern for the self as a practice of freedom’, in Ethics, p. 288.
‘The Hermeneutics of the Subject’, in Ethics, p. 99.
‘The Ethics of the Concern for Self as a Practice of Freedom’, in Ethics, p. 291.
‘Questions of Method’, in Power, pp. 235-6.
‘Le sujet et le pouvoir’ in Dits et écrits II 1976-1988, Paris, 2001, p. 1051 (cited by A.I. Davidson in ‘Introduction’ to Security, Territory, Population, p. xxx).
‘The Ethics of the Concern for Self as a Practice of Freedom’, in Ethics, p. 295.
Ibid. p. 295-6 (emphasis added).
Ibid. p. 298.
There is one occasion on which Foucault appears to adopt an advocacy of fundamental rights which is very much out of keeping with his usual approach: ‘The rules that exist to limit it [i.e. power] can never be stringent enough; the universal principles for dispossessing it of all the occasions it seizes are never sufficiently rigorous. Against power one must always set inviolable laws and unrestricted rights.’ (‘Useless to Revolt?’, in Power, p. 453). However, no other appeals of a similarly universalist and essentialist nature have been discovered in Foucault.
Constitutional Code, vol. I, ed. F. Rosen and J.H. Burns, Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1983 (CW).
‘The Risks of Security’, in Power, p. 366.
Haut de page