Bibliographie
Primary Sources
British Library Add MS 4326, fol. 64-66.
Maseres, Francis, Considerations on the Expediency of Admitting Representatives from the American Colonies in the British House of Commons (London, 1770).
Price, Richard, Observations on the Nature of Civil Liberty, the Principles of Government, and the Justice and Policy of the War with America (London, 1776).
Price, Richard, Observations on the Importance of the American Revolution, and the Means of Making it a Benefit to the World (London, 1784).
Priestley, Joseph, Letters to the Right Honourable Edmund Burke (third edition; Birmingham, 1791).
Smith, Adam, The Theory of Moral Sentiments, eds. D.D. Raphael and A.L. Macfie (Oxford : Oxford University Press, 1976).
Smith, Adam, An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations, eds. R. H. Campbell and A. S. Skinner (Oxford : Oxford University Press, 1976).
Smith, Adam, Correspondence of Adam Smith, eds. Ernest Campbell Mossner and Ian Simpson Ross (Oxford : Oxford University Press, 1977).
Smith, Adam, Lectures on Jurisprudence, eds. D. D. Raphael and P. G. Stein (Oxford : Oxford University Press, 1978).
Tucker, Josiah, Reflections on the Expediency of a Law for the Naturalization of Foreign Protestants, (London, 1751).
Tucker, Josiah, A Brief Essays on the Advantages and Disadvantages which respectively attend France and Great Britain, with regard to Trade (London, 1753 [1749]).
Tucker, Josiah, A Letter to a Friend concerning Naturalizations (London, 1753).
Tucker, Josiah, A Second Letter to a Friend concerning Naturalizations (London, 1753).
Tucker, Josiah, Reflections on the Expediency of Opening the Trade to Turkey (London, 1753).
Tucker, Josiah, The Elements of Commerce, and Theory of Taxes (n.p. ([Bristol?]), 1755).
Tucker, Josiah, Instructions for Travellers (Gloucester, 1757).
Tucker, Josiah, The Manifold Causes of the Increase of the Poor Distinctly Set forth; together with a Set of Proposals for Removing and Preventing some of the Principal Evils, and for Lessening Others (s.n., 1760).
Tucker, Josiah, Four Tracts, Political and Commercial Subjects (Gloucester, 1774).
Tucker, Josiah, An Humble Address and Earnest Appeal to Those Respectable Personages in Great Britain and Ireland (Gloucester, 1775).
Tucker, Josiah, A Letter to Edmund Burke (Gloucester, 1775).
Tucker, Josiah, Tract V. the Respective Pleas and Arguments on the Mother Country, and of the Colonies, Distinctly Set Forth (Gloucester, 1775).
Tucker, Josiah, A Series of Answers to Certain Popular Objections, against Separating from the Rebellious Colonies (Gloucester, 1776).
Tuker, Josiah, Seventeen Sermons on some of the Most Important Points on Natural and Revealed Religion (Gloucester, 1776).
Tucker, Josiah, A Treatise Concerning Civil Government in Three Parts (London, 1781).
Tucker, Josiah, Cui Bono?: Or, an Inquiry, what Benefits Can Arise Either to the English Or the Americans (Gloucester, 1782).
Tucker, Josiah, Reflections on the Present Matters in Dispute between Great Britain and Ireland (Dublin, 1785).
Secondary Sources
Arie, Daisuke, 'Lost in Translation? How Japan’s Intellectuals Translated Utilitarian Writings in the Early Stage of Her Modernization', Revue d’études benthamiennes, 23 (2019).
Armitage, David, The Ideological Origins of the British Empire (Cambridge : Cambridge University Press, 2000).
Baji, Tomohito, The International Thought of Alfred Zimmern: Classicism, Zionism and the Shadow of Commonwealth (Cham : Palgrave Macmillan, 2021).
Berry, Christopher, The Idea of Commercial Society in the Scottish Enlightenment (Edinburgh : Edinburgh University Press, 2013).
Bourke, Richard, Empire and Revolution: Political Life of Edmund Burke (Princeton : Princeton University Press, 2015).
Campbell, T.D. and I.S. Ross, 'The Utilitarianism of Adam Smith's Policy Advice', Journal of the History of Ideas, 42:1 (1981), pp. 73-92.
Canovan, Margaret, 'The Un-Benthamite Utilitarianism of Joseph Priestley', Journal of the History of Ideas, 45: 3 (1984), pp. 435-450.
Dickinson, Harry T., Liberty and Property: Political Ideology in Eighteenth-Century Britain (London and New York : Holmes and Meier Publishers, 1977).
Dickinson, Harry T., 'The Failure of Conciliation: Britain and the American Colonies 1763-1783', The Kyoto Economic Review, 79(2) (2010), pp. 91-109.
Fitzpatrick, Martin, 'Joseph Priestley, Political Philosopher', in Joseph Priestley, Scientist, Philosopher, and Theologian, eds. Isabel Rivers and David L. Wykes (Oxford : Oxford University Press, 2008), pp. 113-143.
Hill, Lisa, 'The Hidden Theology of Adam Smith', European Journal of the History of Economic Thought, 8:1 (2001), pp. 1-29.
Hont, Istvan, 'Adam Smith and the Political Economy of the “Unnatural and Retrograde” Order', in idem, Jealousy of Trade: International Competition and the Nation-State in Historical Perspective (Cambridge, Mss and London : Harvard University Press, 2005).
Hont, Istvan, 'The “Rich Country-Poor Country” Debate in the Scottish Enlightenment', in idem, Jealousy of Trade, Jealousy of Trade: International Competition and the Nation-State in Historical Perspective (Cambridge, Mss and London : Harvard University Press, 2005), pp. 267-322.
Keane, J., Tom Paine: A Political Life (London : Bloomsbury, 1995).
Kobayashi, Noboru, Keizaigakushi Chosakushū 4 (Igirisu Jūshōshugi Kenkyū, 2) [Collected Works of the History of Economic Thought 4 (Studies on British Mercantilism 2)] (Tokyo : Miraisha, 1977) [in Japanese].
Levy, D., 'The partial spectator in the Wealth of Nations: A robust utilitarianism', European Journal of the History of Economic Thought, 2:2 (1995), pp. 299-326.
Matsumoto, Akihito, 'Happiness and Religion: Joseph Priestley’s “Theological Utilitarianism”', The Kyoto Economic Review, 79: 2 (2010), pp. 55-66.
Muthu, Sankar, Enlightenment against Empire (Princeton, N.J. : Princeton University Press, 2003).
Muthu, Sankar, 'Adam Smith’s Critique of International Trading Companies: Theorizing “Globalization” in the Age of Enlightenment', Political Theory, 36 (2008), pp. 185-212.
Muthu, Sankar (ed.), Empire and Modern Political Thought (Cambridge : Cambridge University Press, 2012).
Oslington, Paul ed., Adam Smith as Theologian (London : Routledge, 2011).
Phillipson, Nicholas, Adam Smith: An Enlightened Life (New Haven : Yale University Press, 2010 [Penguin Books, 2011]).
Pitts, Jennifer, A Turn to Empire: The Rise of Imperial Liberalism in Britain and France (Princeton : N.J., Princeton University Press, 2005).
Pocock, J. G. A., 'Hume and the American Revolution: The dying thoughts of a North Briton' in his Virtue, Commerce, and History (Cambridge : Cambridge University Press, 1985).
Pocock, J. G. A., 'Josiah Tucker on Burke, Locke, and Price: A study in the varieties of eighteenth-century conservatism' in his Virtue, Commerce, and History: Essays on Political thought and History, Chiefly in the Eighteenth Century (Cambridge : Cambridge University Press, 1985).
Pocock, J. G. A., The Discovery of Islands: Essays in British History (Cambridge : Cambridge University Press, 2005).
Price, Peter Xavier, 'Liberty, Poverty and Charity in the Political Economy of Josiah Tucker and Joseph Butler', Modern Intellectual History, 16 (2019), pp. 741-770.
Raphael, D. D., 'Hume and Adam Smith on justice and utility', Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 73 (1972) pp. 87-103.
Rashid,Salim, '“He Startled… As If He Saw a Spectre”: Tucker’s Proposal for American Independence', Journal of the History of Ideas, 43: 3 (1982), pp. 439-460.
Rawls, John, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, Mass : Harvard University Press, 1971)
Robertson, John (ed.), A Union for Empire: Political Thought and the British Union of 1707 (Cambridge : Cambridge University Press, 1995).
Rosen, Frederick, 'The idea of utility in Adam Smith’s Theory of Moral Sentiments', History of European Ideas, 26 (2000), pp. 79-103.
Rosen, Frederick., Classical Utilitarianism From Hume to Mill (London : Routledge, 2003).
Ross, Ian Simpson, The Life of Adam Smith, Second Edition (Oxford : Oxford University Press, [1995] 2010).
Schneewind, J.B., The Invention of Autonomy: A History of Modern Moral Philosophy (Cambridge : Cambridge University Press, 1998).
Shelton, George, Dean Tucker and the Eighteenth-Century Economics and Political Thought (New York : Macmillan, 1981).
Skinner, Andrew, 'Adam Smith: the demise of the colonial relationship with America', Cahier d’économie politique, no. 27/28, Libéralisme à l'épreuve (Paris : L’Harmattan, 1996).
Smith, Craig, Adam Smith (Cambridge : Polity Press, 2020).
Stevens, D, 'Adam Smith and the Colonial Disturbances', in Essays on Adam Smith, eds. Andrew S. Skinner and Thomas Wilson (Oxford : Clarendon Press, 1975), pp. 202-217.
Travers, Robert, 'British India as a Problem in Political Economy: Comparing James Steuart and Adam Smith', in Lineages of Empire: The Historical Roots of British Imperial Thought (Oxford : Oxford University Press, 2009), pp. 137-161.
Ueno, Hiroki, 'Does Adam Smith’s Moral Theory Truly Diverge from Humean Utilitarianism?' in Schefczyk, Michael and Schmidt-Petri, Christoph (eds), Utility, Progress, and Technology: Proceedings of the 15th Conference of the International Society for Utilitarian Studies (Karlsruhe : KIT Scientific Publishing, 2021), pp. 305-313.
Ueno, Hiroki, 'Educating a Young Aristocrat during Grand Tour', Journal of Scottish Philosophy, 21 (2023), pp. 75-96.
Ulas Ince, Onur, 'Adam Smith, Settler Colonialism, and Limits of Liberal Anti-imperialism', The Journal of Politics, 83:3 (2021), pp. 1080-1096.
van de Harr, Edwin, 'Adam Smith on Empire and International Relations', in The Oxford Handbook of Adam Smith, eds. Christopher J. Berry, Maria Pia Paganelli and Craig Smith (Oxford : Oxford University Press, 2013).
Williams, David, 'Adam Smith and Colonialism', Journal of International Political Theory, 10 (2014), pp. 283-301
Winch, Donald, 'The science of the legislator: The enlightenment heritage' in The State and Social Investigation in Britain and the United States, eds. M.J. Lancey and M.O. Furner (Cambridge : Cambridge University Press, 1993), pp. 63-94.
Witztum, Amos and Jeffrey T. Young, 'Utilitarianism and the Role of Utility in Adam Smith', The European Journal of the History of Economic Thought, 20:4 (2013), pp. 572-602.
Young, B.W., 'Christianity, Commerce and the Canon: Josiah Tucker and Richard Woodward on Political Economy', History of European Ideas, 22 (1996), pp. 385-400.
Haut de page
Notes
A representative figure of this current, David Armitage, who moved from Cambridge in Britain to the United States, where the study of intellectual history is now entwined with political theory and global history, published seminal work which has rendered this dichotomous question almost invalid, as the ideologies behind the British Empire had already arisen in early-modern Great Britain before the narrowly-defined Age of Enlightenment. See Armitage, David, The ideological Origins of the British Empire (Cambridge : Cambridge University Press, 2000).
Muthu, Sankar, Enlightenment against Empire (Princeton, N.J. : Princeton University Press, 2003); Muthu, Sankar (ed.), Empire and Modern Political Thought (Cambridge : Cambridge University Press, 2012), pp. 5-6.
Pitts, Jennifer, A Turn to Empire: The Rise of Imperial Liberalism in Britain and France (Princeton, N.J. : Princeton University Press, 2005).
Before the nineteenth century, Europeans already regarded native Americans (and Africans) as obviously inferior to themselves, with several (later Aristotelian or Protestant) jurists discussing the possibility and limit of the law of nations and cosmopolitan law. In regard to the peoples of the Orient, East India, and Asia, however, most European literati sufficiently understood how significant the contribution of Asian culture had been to the development of their own civilisation. Before the 'turn to Empire' (in Pitts' words), the Western imperial project tended to focus on constructing 'settlers’ colonies' in the New World, seldom accompanied by the indiscriminate arrogance toward the 'non-West' as a whole. Around the turn to the nineteenth century, however, the Western ambition toward Asia was no longer merely commercial, but also colonialistic, expanding 'dependencies' that had huge native populations with whom the Western immigrants had to co-exist. For this issue, (in addition to the Introduction of this special issue), see Baji, Tomohito, The International Thought of Alfred Zimmern: Classicism, Zionism and the Shadow of Commonwealth (Cham : Palgrave Macmillan, 2021), pp. 211-221.
Williams, David, 'Adam Smith and Colonialism', Journal of International Political Theory, 10 (2014), pp. 283-301; Ulas Ince, Onur, 'Adam Smith, Settler Colonialism, and Limits of Liberal Anti-imperialism', The Journal of Politics, 83:3 (2021), pp. 1080-1096. See also Travers, Robert, 'British India as a Problem in Political Economy: Comparing James Steuart and Adam Smith', in Lineages of Empire: The Historical Roots of British Imperial Thought (Oxford : Oxford University Press, 2009), pp. 137-161.
Campbell, T.D. and I.S. Ross, 'The Utilitarianism of Adam Smith's Policy Advice', Journal of the History of Ideas, 42:1 (1981), pp. 73-92 (at 77, 79). See also Levy, D., 'The partial spectator in the Wealth of Nations: A robust utilitarianism', the European Journal of the History of Economic Thought, 2:2 (1995), pp. 299-326; Schneewind, J.B., The Invention of Autonomy: A History of Modern Moral Philosophy (Cambridge : Cambridge University Press, 1998), p. 391; Rosen, F., 'The idea of utility in Adam Smith’s Theory of Moral Sentiments', History of European Ideas, 26 (2000), pp. 79-103; Rosen, Frederick, Classical Utilitarianism From Hume to Mill (London : Routledge, 2003). For a different view of Smith’s argumentation, see Witztum, Amos and Jeffrey T. Young, 'Utilitarianism and the Role of Utility in Adam Smith', The European Journal of the History of Economic Thought, 20:4 (2013), pp. 572-602; Raphael, D. D., 'Hume and Adam Smith on justice and utility', Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 73 (1972) pp. 87-103. For one of the present authors’ opposition to such an interpretation, see Ueno, Hiroki, 'Does Adam Smith’s Moral Theory Truly Diverge from Humean Utilitarianism?' in Schefczyk, Michael and Schmidt-Petri, Christoph (eds), Utility, Progress, and Technology: Proceedings of the 15th Conference of the International Society for Utilitarian Studies (Karlsruhe : KIT Scientific Publishing, 2021), pp. 305-313. While critical of Witztum and Young’s, Ueno shares their criticism of John Rawls’ interpretation of Adam Smith’s concept of impartial spectator. See, Rawls, J., A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, Mass : Harvard University Press, 1971), p. 27.
Utilitarianism may be the moral theory that has been most consistently misunderstood, particularly in non-Western countries (see, Arie, Daisuke, 'Lost in Translation? How Japan’s Intellectuals Translated Utilitarian Writings in the Early Stage of Her Modernization', Revue d’études benthamiennes, 23 (2019)). It goes without saying that, far from an amoral egoistic position focusing solely on practical usefulness, utilitarianism posits a public and rather altruistic criterion for moral judgement, justifying hedonistic individualism and the pursuit of self-interest under the condition that such collective actions as a whole consequently produce the greatest happiness for the greatest number of people (frequently without intent). While this definition is framed in terms of ethical or political normative theory, it should be underlined that, in the contextualist studies of intellectual history, utilitarian ideas and ideologies were either unconsciously or preconsciously employed as a 'paradigmatic' language by many authors including those, discussed in the present article, without being systematically expressed or theorised. For the purpose of the following argument here, it should also be noted that, theoretically speaking, utilitarian moral theory has its own view of justice related to common good, while the nature of their framing is of a distinct quality from the so-called Lockean or deontological conception of justice and right. The latter’s fundamental characteristic lies in its categorical and unconditional morality that is justified separately from happiness or good as consequences of action.
J. G. A. Pocock alludes only briefly to the common utilitarian ground to Smith and Tucker (and Hume): 'The key to Tucker’s mind must be found in the unity he effected between the need for economic freedom and that for submission to civil authority. The first of these principles convinced him (with David Hume) that those who made war for commercial empire were wicked madmen, and (with Adam Smith) that to maintain empire in order to regulate colonial economies was costly futility' (Pocock, J. G. A., 'Josiah Tucker on Burke, Locke, and Price: A study in the varieties of eighteenth-century conservatism' in his Virtue, Commerce, and History: Essays on Political thought and History, Chiefly in the Eighteenth Century (Cambridge : Cambridge University Press, 1985) p. 161).
To quickly mention the order of our argument, which addresses Smith first and then Tucker: one may draw attention to the fact that Tucker, as the paper shall later discuss in detail, expressed his criticism of mercantilism by suggesting the reasonableness of the separation plan, long before Smith did. With this fact suggesting the considerable possibility that Tucker himself even influenced Smith (possibly via Hume) and not vise-versa on the issues, however, we shall begin with the long-discussed Smith before Tucker in order to set up a basic framework for clarifying their similarities and differences.
Several alternatives to be compared with Tucker are surely present in the Scottish Enlightenment in relation to our subject, and the combination selected here is not intended to be exclusive. For example, Adam Ferguson is another fascinating case worthy of investigation, due to his life-long commitment to the imperial project being much more explicit (which will be tackled by Craig Smith’s contribution in our special issue, entitled 'Adam Ferguson on Trade and Empire'), while Hume was likely to be less attracted by the colonists’ causes in North America than Smith, due to his political stance being even more similar to Tucker’s. Generally speaking, Smith simply presents a more natural choice than other Scots here for comparison with Tucker, based on the situation with previous literature.
For recent arguments from the international relations theory, see van de Harr, Edwin, 'Adam Smith on Empire and International Relations', in The Oxford Handbook of Adam Smith, eds. Christopher J. Berry, Maria Pia Paganelli and Craig Smith (Oxford : Oxford University Press, 2013). In this special issue, Shinji Nohara’s article 'Adam Smith’s colonial thought on South Africa' is expanding the scope beyond North America in a search for the correlation between Smith and colonialism.
Ross, Ian Simpson, The Life of Adam Smith, Second Edition (Oxford : Oxford University Press, [1995] 2010), pp. 284-285 and chapter 17; cf. Phillipson, Nicholas, Adam Smith: An Enlightened Life (New Haven : Yale University Press, 2010 [Penguin Books, 2011]), pp. 211-213.
Smith, Adam, An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations, eds. R. H. Campbell and A. S. Skinner (Oxford : Oxford University Press, 1976), Book VI, chapter 7.
Pocock, J. G. A., 'Hume and the American Revolution: The dying thoughts of a North Briton' in his Virtue, Commerce, and History (Cambridge : Cambridge University Press, 1985), p. 139.
While Hume’s advocacy of American independence tends to chiefly be framed in terms of criticism of the instability of London domestic politics, Smith also roughly shares Hume’s critical viewpoint regarding factionalism (although Hume’s tone in his private correspondence is far more aggressive). See Pocock, J., 'American Revolution', pp. 137-138: 'When empire was a popular cause it meant the expansion of liberty and faction at the expense of reason and authority. Hume wanted to see the Americans independent not because he thought the London radicals right but because he thought them foolish and wicked, like their evil angel Pitt [i.e. William Pitt], and wanted to see them deprived of their rallying cry. There are some remarkably splenetic passages in the letters, in which Hume hopes to see Americans in revolt, London depopulated, and authority restored to the nobility and gentry of both kingdoms. Empire breeds faction, and faction fanaticism'.
Smith, A., Wealth of Nations, IV.vii.b.60, p. 589
Muthu, Enlightenment against Empire; Muthu, Sankar, 'Adam Smith’s Critique of International Trading Companies: Theorizing “Globalization” in the Age of Enlightenment', Political Theory, 36 (2008), pp. 185-212.
Smith, A., Wealth of Nations, IV.vii.b.58-59, p. 588.
Smith, A., Wealth of Nations, IV.vii.a.17, p. 562. He described it as similar to 'the absurd idea of the philosopher’s stone'. Cf. IV.vii.a.18-19.
While Smith’s distinction between the laws of justice and conveniencies is at the centre of his framing natural jurisprudence and 'polis' (from which political economy is derived), this does not denote that his interest finally moved to the economic analysis to come to make light of the morality of justice. On the contrary, his inquiry in the Wealth of Nations should be understood as attempting to demonstrate that what is right (or at least permissible) in terms of the sense of justice normally corresponds to what is best for the improvement of human welfare in 'the system of natural liberty', suggesting a conception of justice founded upon the utilitarian basis. In the Wealth of Nations, Smith sometimes employs the language of natural rights when discussing whether the legal institutions at issue are beneficial or harmful to most of the people. See, for instance, Smith, A., Wealth of Nations, IV.vii.b.44, p. 582. On the same page, Smith also mentions the mercantilist prohibitions as 'impertinent badges of slavery […] in their present state of improvement', which is reminiscent of his renowned criticism of modern slavery on the grounds of both natural rights and utilitarian logic. This point will be mentioned later in this section.
Skinner, Andrew, 'Adam Smith : the demise of the colonial relationship with America', Cahier d’économie politique, no. 27/28, Libéralisme à l'épreuve (Paris : L’Harmattan, 1996), pp. 122-124.
Skinner, A., 'Demise', p. 114; Stevens, D, 'Adam Smith and the Colonial Disturbances', in Essays on Adam Smith, eds. Andrew S. Skinner and Thomas Wilson (Oxford : Clarendon Press, 1975), pp. 202-217.
For the details, see Ueno, Hiroki, 'Educating a Young Aristocrat during Grand Tour', Journal of Scottish Philosophy, 21 (2023), pp. 75-96, section 5. Cf. Winch, Donald, 'The science of the legislator: The enlightenment heritage' in The State and Social Investigation in Britain and the United States, eds. M.J. Lancey and M.O. Furner (Cambridge : Cambridge University Press, 1993), pp. 63-94.
Smith, A., Wealth of Nations, IV.vii.c.60, p. 612; cf. IV.vii.b.49, p. 584.
Smith, A., Wealth of Nations, IV.vii.c.62, p. 613.
Smith, Craig, Adam Smith (Cambridge : Polity Press, 2020), pp. 137-138.
According to Smith, although the American colonies appeared to be free from heavy direct taxes, the monopoly imposed by the mercantilists substantially means 'a very grievous tax upon the colonies' (Smith, A., Wealth of Nations, IV.vii.c.67, p. 618).
Smith, A., Wealth of Nations, IV.vii.c.67, p. 618.
Smith discusses that free trade within the imperial territory is beneficial to the general wealth of the nation by restraining the profits of commercial capitals through competition between them. See Smith, A., Wealth of Nations, IV.vii.b.24, pp. 576-577.
Keane, J., Tom Paine: A Political Life (London : Bloomsbury, 1995), pp. 257-8.
Smith, C., Adam Smith, p. 153.
Dickinson, Harry T., 'The Failure of Conciliation: Britain and the American Colonies 1763-1783', The Kyoto Economic Review, 79(2) (2010), pp. 9-10, cf. pp. 4-6; cf. Dickinson, Harry T., Liberty and Property: Political Ideology in Eighteenth-Century Britain (London and New York : Holmes and Meier Publishers, 1977), chapter 6. Smith himself clearly disagreed with the colonists’ criticism of the idea of virtual representation in the Wealth of Nations. See Smith, A., Wealth of Nations, IV.vii.c.79, p. 625.
Smith, A., Wealth of Nations, IV.vii.c.67, pp. 617-618.
See Smith, A., Wealth of Nations, IV.vii.c.69-70, pp. 619-620. Cf. Dickinson, H. T., 'Failure of Conciliation', pp. 9-10.
Smith, A., Wealth of Nations, IV.vii.c.77, p. 624.
Smith understands considerable differences between their logic and his own vision of restructuring the imperial taxation system. See Smith, A., Wealth of Nations, IV.vii.c.74-75, p. 622.
Pocock, J. G. A., The Discovery of Islands: Essays in British History (Cambridge : Cambridge University Press, 2005), pp. 105-106, 145-148, 171-173, 194-205, 220-226, 234-235.
In the consolidation plan, Smith highly recommends the incorporation union modelled out of the new Anglo-Scottish relation since 1707 and, as shall be addressed later, this is also applied to his resolution to the Irish question.
For qualification, it should be mentioned that there were several plans suggested by the American side that searched for the possibility of establishing a more integrated legislative body covering the whole empire, such as Benjamin Franklin’s 'Albany Plan' of 1754 and Joseph Galloway’s plan for a 'grand legislative union' (1774). According to Andrew Skinner, Smith’s consolidation plan was broadly in line with these visions (Skinner, A., 'Demise', pp. 124-125).
Smith, Adam, Correspondence of Adam Smith, eds. Ernest Campbell Mossner and Ian Simpson Ross (Oxford : Oxford University Press, 1977), pp. 377-385.
According to J. G. A. Pocock, this utilitarian view of American independence is shared with both Tucker and Hume as well: the need for submission to civil authority 'persuaded Tucker (with both Hume and Smith) that if the Americans would not submit to the authority of Parliament they should become separate and independent states - not indeed because they possessed any of the rights they were claiming, which would soon lead them to declare their independence, but because they were a set of dangerous anarchs with whom Britain, for both commercial and civil reasons, should have as little as possible to do. Neither Hume nor Smith was far from sharing the belief that independence was desirable, not as an American right but as a British convenience, and Hume agreed with Tucker that it would spike the guns of the potentially revolutionary agitators in London and Middlesex; but the dean of Gloucester proclaimed at the top of his voice what Smith knew was not politically practical to say before public opinion was ready for it' (Pocock, J. G. A., 'Tucker on Burke, Locke, and Price', pp. 161-2).
Pocock, J., 'American Revolution', p. 138: 'Like Adam Smith in Scotland and Josiah Tucker in England, Hume desired American independence for the strictly Tory reason - Tory, that is, as that word would be used in the generation following his own - that empire had come to be a radical burden on the structure of British politics. The Whig regime had been among other things a balance between the forces of landed oligarchy, making for stability, and London commerce, making for empire. Faced with a choice between the two, the conservative mind would sacrifice empire to stability without hesitation - especially if it meant jettisoning Pitt’s and Wilkes’s radical Londoners along the way'.
Smith, A., Wealth of Nations, IV.vii.c.66, p. 617.
Smith, A., Wealth of Nations, IV.vii.c.66, p. 617.
On the relationship between justice and utility in Adam Smith, see also Ueno, H., 'Does Adam Smith’s Moral Theory Truly Diverge from Humean Utilitarianism?'.
Smith, A., Wealth of Nations, IV.vii.c.66, p. 617.
Smith, A., Wealth of Nations, IV.vii.c.44, p. 606.
Smith, Adam, The Theory of Moral Sentiments, eds. D.D. Raphael and A.L. Macfie (Oxford : Oxford University Press [Clarendon Press], 1976) VI.ii.2.18, p. 233. An excellent elucidation on the matter of Smith and Physiocrats can be found in Hont, Istvan, 'Adam Smith and the Political Economy of the “Unnatural and Retrograde” Order', in idem, Jealousy of Trade: International Competition and the Nation-State in Historical Perspective (Cambridge, Mss and London : Harvard University Press, 2005).
Smith, A., Wealth of Nations, IV.vii.c.44, p. 606.
For example, see Dickinson, H. T., 'Failure of Conciliation'.
This expression is derived from the title of the following collection of essays: Robertson, John (ed.), A Union for Empire: Political Thought and the British Union of 1707 (Cambridge : Cambridge University Press, 1995). See also Armitage, D., The Ideological Origins.
Smith, A., Wealth of Nations, V.iii.89, p. 944.
Smith, A., Wealth of Nations, V.iii.89, p. 944.
Phillipson, N., Adam Smith, pp. 235-236.
Smith, A., Wealth of Nations, IV.vii.c.90-91, p. 631; cf. IV.vii.b.22-24, pp. 575-577:'Monopolies of this kind are properly established against the very nation which erects them. The greater part of that nation are thereby not only excluded from a trade to which it might be convenient for them to turn some part of their stock, but are obliged to buy the goods which that trade deals in, somewhat dearer than if it was open and free to all their countrymen'.
Smith, A., Wealth of Nations, IV.vii.c.102-104, pp. 637-638: 'Nothing, however, can be more directly contrary to the real interest of those companies, considered as the sovereigns of the countries which they have conquered, than this destructive plan. In almost all countries the revenue of the sovereign is drawn from that of the people. The greater the revenue of the people, therefore, the greater the annual produce of their land and labour, the more they can afford to the sovereign. It is his interest, therefore, to increase as much as possible that annual produce. […]. But a company of merchants are, it seems, incapable of considering themselves as sovereigns, even after they have become such'.
Cooperative aspects of the principles of public utility and natural justice in Smith should be underlined from this article’s point of view. What is characteristic of his critique of slavery lies in synthesising the two. Not every natural lawyer (even including John Locke) is against slavery, and Gershom Carmichael, the predecessor to Smith as the chair of moral philosophy at Glasgow, was rather an exception who categorically declined the right of possessing slaves because of its violation of basic natural rights. To this modern moral judgement did Smith add another powerful argument against slavery, which is a utilitarian critique: 'Smith’s emphasis is on the fact that slavery was economically unproductive; the judgment of the 'badness' of slavery is immediately illustrated by the fact that a free man works better than a slave' (Berry, Christopher, The Idea of Commercial Society in the Scottish Enlightenment (Edinburgh : Edinburgh University Press, 2013), p. 125). See Smith, A., Wealth of Nations, III.ii.9, p. 387. While his utilitarian perspective on slavery does not exclude the language of natural rights at all, Smith’s stance diverges from the Kantian deontologist ethics according to which the natural rights should be defended regardless of whether slavery is in reality harmful to public welfare or not. Smith’s political economy instead attempts to demonstrate how and under what condition anything wrong from the natural sense of justice is at the same time contrary to public welfare as well.
For an overview of Tucker’s engagement with the American affairs, see Shelton, George, Dean Tucker and the Eighteenth Century Economics and Political Thought (New York: Macmillan, 1981), chap. 8; Rashid,Salim, '“He Startled … As If He Saw a Spectre”: Tucker’s Proposal for American Independence ', Journal of the History of Ideas, 43: 3 (1982), pp. 439-460.
For Tucker's Christian morality, see Price, Peter Xavier, 'Liberty, Poverty and Charity in the Political Economy of Josiah Tucker and Joseph Butler', Modern Intellectual History, 16 (2019), pp. 741-770; Young, B.W., 'Christianity, Commerce and the Canon: Josiah Tucker and Richard Woodward on Political Economy', History of European Ideas, 22 (1996), pp. 385-400.
On this, see especially, Price, P., 'Liberty, Poverty and Charity in the Political Economy of Josiah Tucker and Joseph Butler'.
Tucker, Josiah, A Brief Essays on the Advantages and Disadvantages which respectively attend France and Great Britain, with regard to Trade (London, 1753), pp. 95-96. The first and shorter edition was published in 1749 under the same title. See also Kobayashi, Noboru, Keizaigakushi Chosakushū 4 (Igirisu Jūshōshugi Kenkyū, 2) [Collected Works of the History of Economic Thought 4 (Studies on British Mercantilism 2)] (Tokyo : Miraisha, 1977) [in Japanese], pp. 99-100.
On this see, for example, Kobayashi, N., Collected Works of the History of Economic Thought 4, pp. 40-41.
Tucker, Josiah, A Series of Answers to Certain Popular Objections, against Separating from the Rebellious Colonies (Gloucester, 1776), p. xiii.
Tucker, Josiah, A Letter to Edmund Burke (Gloucester, 1775).
Maseres, Francis, Considerations on the Expediency of Admitting Representatives from the American Colonies in the British House of Commons (London, 1770).
Tucker, Josiah, Four Tracts, Political and Commercial Subjects (Gloucester, 1774), pp. 164-202. On this, see also Rashid, S., 'Tucker’s Proposal for American Independence', pp. 445-447.
Correspondence of Adam Smith, 380-1 ; Tucker, J., Four Tracts, pp. 196-201 (quotation at 197).
Tucker, J., Four Tracts, pp. 201-2.
Tucker, J., Four Tracts, pp. 172-196.
Tucker, Josiah, Tract V : The Respective Pleas and Arguments of the Mother Country, and of the Colonies, Distinctly Set Forth (Gloucester, 1775), p. 9.
Tucker, J., Four Tracts, pp. 203, 210-212.
Tucker, J., Four Tracts, pp. 218-220.
Tucker, Josiah, An Humble Address and Earnest Appeal to Those Respectable Personages in Great Britain and Ireland (Gloucester, 1775), p. 42; Tucker, Series of Answers, 1776, p. 75. The distance between mother countries and colonies are significant as he wrote to Dr. Birch in 1755: 'In regard to the Commercial: if a Colony is so far distant, as it the Mother Country can reap no Benefit from it'. As for the French colonies in Canada, he wrote in the same letter: 'their settlements in Canada are a dead expence & a continual Drain to them; that they never did, & never can answer any of those important Ends of Commerce for which Colonies ought to be settled'. See British Library Add MS 4326, fol. 64.
Tucker, J., Four Tracts, tract I (esp., p. 28).
Tucker, J., Humble Address and Earnest Appeal to Those Respectable Personages in Great Britain and Ireland, p. 44.
Tucker, J., Tract V, pp. 16-21.
Hont, I., 'The “Rich Country-Poor Country” Debate in the Scottish Enlightenment', in idem, Jealousy of Trade, pp. 267-322.
Josiah Tucker to Lord Kames (26 December 1763), quoted in Hont, I., 'The “Rich Country-Poor Country” Debate in the Scottish Enlightenment', in idem, Jealousy of Trade, p. 295.
Tucker, Josiah, The Elements of Commerce, and Theory of Taxes (n.p. ([Bristol?]), 1755), p. 88.
Hont, I., 'The “Rich Country-Poor Country” Debate in the Scottish Enlightenment', in idem, Jealousy of Trade, p. 294.
On this, see Kobayashi, N., Collected Works of the History of Economic Thought 4, p. 99.
Tucker, J., Elements of Commerce and Taxes, p. 124.
Smith, A., Wealth of Nations, IV.vii.b.44, p. 582. See also Smith, Adam, Lectures on Jurisprudence, eds. D. D. Raphael and P. G. Stein (Oxford : Oxford University Press, 1978), p. 8 (24 December 1762).
Tucker, J., Elements of Commerce and Taxes, passim; idem, Reflections on the Expediency of Opening the Trade to Turkey (London, 1753), p. 4.
Tucker, J., Reflections on the Expediency of Opening the Trade to Turkey, pp. 6-20.
Tucker, J., Elements of Commerce and Taxes, pp. 120-123.
Tucker, J., Four Tracts, pp. 213-215: 'And this Country in particular would have found the happy Effects of them to a much greater Degree than it now doth, were they not counter-acted by our Luxury, our Gambling, our frequent ruinous and expensive Wars, our Colony-Drains, and by that ill-gotten, and ill-spent Wealth, which was obtained by robbing, plundering, and starving the poor defenceless Natives of the East-Indies' (at 215 note). In the summer of 1755, Tucker already insisted: 'In short I can see no Cause for engaging in a War to get an Extent of Territory in American beyond the allegaheny Mountains.: The greatest misfortune, that can befall a State into have a Country without inhabitants: And if we could drive the French out of all N. America, it would be the most fatal step we could take.' (Tucker to Dr. Birch (1 August 1755), British Library Add MS 4326).
Tucker, Josiah, Reflections on the Present Matters in Dispute between Great Britain and Ireland (Dublin, 1785), p. 18.
Tucker, J., A Brief Essay on Advantages and Disadvantages, 1753, p. ii ('Introduction').
Tucker, Josiah, Cui Bono?: Or, an Inquiry, what Benefits Can Arise Either to the English Or the Americans (Gloucester, 1782), pp. 34, 46 (quotation at 46).
Tucker, Josiah, A Treatise Concerning Civil Government in Three Parts (London, 1781), pp. 183-184; idem, Letter to Edmund Burke, p. 23.
Tucker, Letter to Edmund Burke, p. 23: 'Nay, I think it is demonstrable, that domestic pr predial Slavery would be found, on a fair Calculation, to be the most onerous and expensive Mode of cultivating Land, and of raising Produce, that could be devised'.
Tuker, Josiah, Seventeen Sermons on some of the Most Important Points on Natural and Revealed Religion (Gloucester, 1776), pp. 138, 141.
Tucker, J., Seventeen Sermons, 1776, pp. 142, 144. See also idem, Letter to Edmund Burke, p. 23.
Tucker, J., A Brief Essay on Advantages and Disadvantages, 1753, pp. 23-36.
Tucker, J., Humble Address and Earnest Appeal to Those Respectable Personages in Great Britain and Ireland, p. 91.
Bourke, Richard, Empire and Revolution: Political Life of Edmund Burke (Princeton : Princeton University Press, 2015), pp. 15-16.
Tucker, J., Elements of Commerce and Theory of Tax, p. 107.
Tucker, Josiah, Instructions for Travellers (Gloucester, 1757), p. 36.
Tucker, J., Elements of Commerce and Theory of Tax, p. 134.
Tucker, J., Elements of Commerce and Theory of Tax, p. 97.
Tucker, J., Reflections on the Present Matters in Dispute between Great Britain and Ireland, p. 39.
Correspondence of Adam Smith, p. 382.
Tucker, J., A Brief Essay on Trade, 1749, p. 36.
Tucker, J., A Brief Essay on Trade, 1749, pp. 58-9.
Tucker, Josiah, The Manifold Causes of the Increase of the Poor Distinctly Set forth; together with a Set of Proposals for Removing and Preventing some of the Principal Evils, and for Lessening Others (s.n., 1760), p. 8.
Tucker, Josiah, Reflections on the Expediency of a Law for the Naturalization of Foreign Protestants, p. 36 [second pagination] (London, 1751).
Tucker, Josiah, A Letter to a Friend concerning Naturalizations (London, 1753); idem, A Second Letter to a Friend concerning Naturalizations (London, 1753).
Price, Richard, Observations on the Nature of Civil Liberty, the Principles of Government, and the Justice and Policy of the War with America (London, 1776), pp. 101-102.
Price, Richard, Observations on the Importance of the American Revolution, and the Means of Making it a Benefit to the World (London, 1784), pp. 6-7.
On this, see Oslington, Paul ed., Adam Smith as Theologian (London : Routledge, 2011).
Smith, A., Theory of Moral Sentiments, I.ii.4, II. Iii.3.2, pp. 36, 105-6 quoted by Hill, Lisa, 'The Hidden Theology of Adam Smith', European Journal of the History of Economic Thought, 8:1 (2001), pp. 1-29 (at 11, 16).
On this, for instance, see Fitzpatrick, Martin, 'Joseph Priestley, Political Philosopher', in Joseph Priestley, Scientist, Philosopher, and Theologian, eds. Isabel Rivers and David L. Wykes (Oxford : Oxford University Press, 2008), pp. 113-143.
Priestley, Joseph, Letters to the Right Honourable Edmund Burke (third edition; Birmingham, 1791), pp. 71, 69.
For Priestley as a utilitarian, for instance, Canovan, Margaret, 'The Un-Benthamite Utilitarianism of Joseph Priestley', Journal of the History of Ideas, 45: 3 (1984), pp. 435-450; Matsumoto, Akihito, 'Happiness and Religion: Joseph Priestley’s “Theological Utilitarianism”', The Kyoto Economic Review, 79: 2 (2010), pp. 55-66.
Smith, A., Wealth of Nations, p. 626-7., IV.vii.c.80, pp. 626-7.
Haut de page