Rights beyond the Unencumbered Self: Property-Freedom and Federation against Property-Theft and Centralisation
Résumés
Cet article propose de lire Le commun de la liberté (2022) de Catherine Colliot-Thélène comme une contribution majeure à la manière nouvelle de faire de la philosophie politique propre à ce que l’on peut appeler les « Lumières radicales ». Il part de l’idée que le livre s’inscrit dans le même projet politico-philosophique que La démocratie sans « demos » (2011), celui de reconstruire la démocratie sur une base nouvelle et radicale. Colliot-Thélène propose une défense audacieuse de l’individualisme méthodologique des droits dont elle fait l’élément clé de la grammaire de la politique démocratique, en même temps qu’elle examine les lacunes des systèmes démocratiques existants du point de vue de deux figures symptomatiques, le pauvre et le réfugié. La deuxième partie de la contribution aborde trois aspects qui sont au cœur du Commun de la liberté, à savoir la conception de la propriété, la conception de la citoyenneté et des statuts personnels, et la théorie des droits.
Plan
Haut de pageTexte intégral
- 1 P.-J. Proudhon, Théorie de la propriété, Paris, L’Harmattan, 1997, p. 50.
Il faut, pour que la propriété entre dans la société, qu’elle en reçoive le timbre, la légalisation, la sanction. Or je dis que sanctionner, légaliser la propriété, lui donner le caractère juridique qui seul peut la rendre respectable, cela ne se peut faire que sous la condition d’une balance, et qu’en dehors de cette réciprocité nécessaire, ni les décrets du prince, ni le consentement des masses, ni les licences de l’Église, ni le verbiage des philosophes sur le moi et le non-moi n’y servent de rien.1
1This contribution has two main goals. The first is to offer a reading of Catherine Colliot-Thélène’s Le commun de la liberté which regards the book as a major contribution to the renewal of the way of doing political philosophy characteristic of what may be called the “radical enlightenment”. The second is to engage with three aspects which are at the core of Le commun de la liberté, namely the conception of property, the conception of citizenship and of personal statuses, and the theory of rights.
Renewing the politico-philosophical project of radical enlightenment
2In this first section, I stress the fundamental continuity between La démocratie sans “demos”, Colliot-Thélène’s previous book, and Le commun de la liberté. The latter, in ways more than one, provides the main elements of a theory of democracy which is as much detached not only from the ethnos, but also from the demos. Then I rehearse the strong case for the radical enlightenment put forward in the book. This takes the form of a defence of normative individualism (in its turn combining a strong conception of the individual as right holder – not least of a right to dignity which cannot simply be trumped by other considerations, concerns and interests – and of rights themselves). But not only. A radical form comes hand in hand with a radical substance. Thus the core of the book proposes a very strong conception of private property as the key vehicle through which individuals gain access to the commons. Which entails, in its turn, specific attention to the symptomatic figures of the poor and the refugee. Then I briefly rehearse the reasons why we need so urgently to put forward a case for radical enlightenment, subject as it is to what may be called a pincer-attack, from the neo-ordo liberals (with even the so-called anarcho-capitalistic discourse making a retour) and from the “progressives” who attack rights in the name of the shortcomings not of rights per se, but of “bourgeois rights”.
A project coming to its completion: reading Le commun de la liberté together with La démocratie sans “demos”
- 2 C. Colliot-Thélène, Le commun de la liberté. Du droit de propriété au devoir d’hospitalité, Paris, (...)
- 3 C. Colliot-Thélène, La démocratie sans “demos”, Paris, Presses universitaires de France, 2011.
3It seems to me that it is important to stress the strong continuity there is between Le commun de la liberté,2 Colliot-Thélène’s previous book, and La démocratie sans “demos”.3
- 4 Ibid., p. 10.
4The core purpose of Le commun de la liberté was to offer its reader a rendering of democratic theory rid of the ideal of “self-legislation”. This is indeed a bold project. At the very beginning of La démocratie sans “demos”, Colliot-Thélène characterised self-legislation as a mystification. She went so far as to compare its role in democratic theory with that played by the divine origin of power in absolutist theories.4 This is said to be so because self-legislation leads unavoidably to the creation of a mask, the mask of the demos. Something which is to be regretted for two reasons. The first is because it results in cloaking in plain sight the structural difference between the rulers and the ruled, that is, hiding the fact that not all rule, but only some rule. The second is that a demos-based democracy relies on the ludicrous assumption that political communities are closed communities, something which was never true and is even less so now. Founding politics on purely abstract ideas of the collective, even if in its civic version of the demos, leads objectively to create the room for exclusionary politics and policies. Or what is the same, self-legislation leads to the mask of the demos, and the mask of the demos seeds the grounds of exclusionary politics and policies, even when such mask is not combined with exclusionary, pre-political elements (the ethnos). This is objectively so, no matter what are the intentions of the advocates of this or that demos-based theory of democracy.
A vindication of radical enlightenment
- 5 J. Israel, A Revolution of the Mind: Radical Enlightenment and the Intellectual Origins of Modern D (...)
5Both La démocratie sans “demos” and Le commun de la liberté, but very particularly the latter, articulate a powerful defence and vindication of the politico-philosophical project of the radical enlightenment, as famously and perceptively defined by Jonathan Israel.5 To put it differently, they make the case for a radical transformation not only of the forms of politics, including its institutional structures, but also (and mainly) of its substantive matter and content. This implies that Le commun de la liberté appeals to a transformation of the social and the economic structures, that is, the very way in which individuals relate to each other concretely in the “in-between” that is politics.
6At the core of this vision of the radical enlightenment we find a staunch defence of normative individualism, which is articulated in a very specific conception of rights as the fundamental grammar of politics. Colliot-Thélène stressed in La démocratie sans “demos” that the individual as right holder and individual rights as fundamental legal and political positions not only constitute the key pivot around which democratic theory turns, but also provide the foundation of truly egalitarian politics. Such a thesis is brought to full fruition in Le commun de la liberté, as we can read at the very beginning of the book:
- 6 C. Colliot-Thélène, Le commun de la liberté…, p. 11 (all translations are mine).
It is my claim that the concepts of right holder [sujet de droit] and of subjective right have an emancipatory potential: they are so closely bond to the modern understanding of freedom that it is not only necessary, but urgent, to defend them, because this freedom is menaced by the contemporary transformations of the modes of political governance.6
7Three implications follow.
- 7 See F. D’Agostino, Chomsky’s System of Ideas, Oxford, Clarendon, 1986, p. 11-12.
- 8 Also, as we will see, citizenship without ethnos, and property without capitalism and without capit (...)
8First, this entails a radical vindication of the centrality of the individual in politico-philosophical and legal terms, in line with the view of what has been aptly called “methodological individualism”.7 Our political theory has become so confused that it is necessary to immediately add that such a defence is not concomitant with any form of reductionist, even less “unencumbered”, “self-regarding”, egotistic individualism, but rather one which comes hand in hand with a deep commitment to equal liberty. A commitment which necessarily relies on the predisposition towards sympathy and benevolence which bonds individuals into societies, associations and groupings. Or what is the same, Colliot-Thélène’s individual is a political animal, but one whose polity fully respects the freedom and dignity of each of its members (and, crucially, hosts, including all forced migrants). This political capacity is indeed what accounts for the very possibility of individuals engaging into democratic politics without the need of clothing their bonds with the “mask” of the demos.8
- 9 C. Colliot-Thélène, Le commun de la liberté…, p. 61.
- 10 Ibid., p. 68.
- 11 See paradigmatically N. MacCormick, “Children’s Rights: A Test-Case for Theories of Right”, ARSP: A (...)
9Second, the grammar of democratic politics without the demos is structured around rights, not duties. This is essential not only in theoretical terms, but also in political terms. On the first account, the very point of discussing whether Immanuel Kant’s theory of rights is not duty-based is precisely to show that the ultimate foundation of rights is not to be found in any duty. The principle of which the categorical imperative is an expression, Colliot-Thélène emphasises, “is the necessary representation of what is proper to the human being, namely her freedom”.9 Indeed, Kant’s objective is to render intelligible “the specific modality of a constraint compatible with freedom”.10 At the beginning, therefore, we have freedom, and therefore, we have the creative possibilities of freedom, also in political terms. On the second account, structuring the grammar of politics around the equal rights of all guarantees that rights keep their critical edge. In such a way, we pre-empt the instrumental use of some rights (property as a means of exploitation of others) to defend the status quo. In so doing, Colliot-Thélène vindicates a long tradition of pre-post-modern thought which assigns primacy to rights while emphasising the importance of the duties which render possible the equal enjoyment of rights, from Herbert Hart and Norberto Bobbio to Neil MacCormick.11
- 12 A. Shachar, The Birthright Lottery: Citizenship and Global Inequality, Cambridge, Harvard Universit (...)
10Third, Colliot-Thélène defines the project of radical enlightenment by reference to the material and not merely formal and institutional dimension of democracy, by means of focusing on two of the main causes of discrimination and exclusion, namely, class / socio-economic position and nationality (“the birthright lottery”12).
- 13 C. Colliot-Thélène, Le commun de la liberté…, p. 136. The term “cannibal capitalism”, of Weberian a (...)
- 14 J. Locke, Two Treatises of Government [1689], P. Laslett (ed.), Cambridge, Cambridge University Pre (...)
- 15 R. Nozick, Anarchy, State and Utopia, New York, Basic Books, 1974, chapter 7. For the right-based c (...)
11Her reading of Kant, contained in chapters 1 and 2 of Le commun de la liberté, rescues the normative potential of Kant’s theory of property from Kant’s specific rendering of it in The Metaphysics of Morals, while her reading of Karl Marx’s critique of property in chapter 3 not only shows the way in which Marx’s thought evolves over time (from the Jewish Question to Capital), but also distils the core of his critique, which consists in the elucidation of what we may refer as the cannibalistic proclivities of capitalistic property, or what is the same, its devouring through infinite and ever greater process of accumulation the very societal and normative foundations of the institution of property.13 This by itself implies a major contribution to both the critique of property as an exclusionary device (la propriété-vol, to say it with the magnificent slogan coined by Pierre-Joseph Proudhon in What Is Property?, the first of his memoirs on property) and the defence of a conception of property as enabler of freedom (la propriété-liberté, as also suggested by Proudhon in the set of memoirs on property, written from 1840 to 1842, and later in his Théorie de la propriété, only published after his death). Democratic property, or what is the same, property divorced from the monarchical principle, is to be understood as a claim that ensures access to the commons. Not as a mere desideratum, but in tangible terms, providing a real guarantee of access to the resources needed so that all have an equal enjoyment of their freedom. This implies not only a radical critique of really existing institutions of private property, but one that is based on the fundamental claim that such a practice is simply incoherent with our fundamental political understandings and commitments. On the one hand, the title to property is said to be gained through labour, i.e. through the blending of one’s labour with material things, which would become in such a way the property of the labourer. On the other hand, the way in which bourgeois property actually operates results in the very expropriation of the labourers. This tension is clearly at work in the paradigmatic defence of private property, contained in John Locke’s chapter 5 of the Second Treatise of Government.14 The connection between property and labour critically depends on the limits to appropriation which Locke introduces through the so-called provisos: one’s appropriation must not foreclose the possibility of other members of the polity satisfying their material needs through further actions of appropriation; and one cannot appropriate what is not in a position to consume. However, once money is introduced in the second half of the chapter (something unavoidable if Locke wants to keep the argument relevant: which capitalist economy can function without money, more specifically without a form of “bourgeois” money such as Locke’s?), these provisos basically lose any bindingness, not least because the “openness” of the system to new appropriation is said to be satisfied through the new frontier of financial assets. As a result, there is basically no longer any limit to appropriation. But once this is the case, a fatal divorce of property and labour materialises. The title of property becomes the legal technology through which those who do not work, but hold capital via money, can acquire more money (the money that breeds money), extracting it via waged labour or financial mediation from the actual workers. Attempts at updating Locke (Robert Nozick in his Anarchy, State and Utopia) do not so much solve the quandary as provide further layers of window-dressing in the form of a theory which pretends to offer a “rights-based” defence of a neoliberal socio-economic vision which unavoidably leads to expropriation with the help of the legal technology of capitalistic property.15
12This is combined, as just anticipated, with a powerful reconsideration of the “figures of exclusion” on the basis of wealth (socio-economic exclusion) and place of birth (through migration and asylum policies).
- 16 C. Colliot-Thélène, Le commun de la liberté…, p. 155 sq.
- 17 For a similar critique of the welfare state as a managerial device which ends up licencing corporat (...)
13There is a very powerful and strong critique of the welfare state16 to the extent that it is intended as an instrumental social pacifier, as the very way of stabilising a non-democratic political order, a society in which there is no coordinated exercise of public autonomy, but rather monarchical or oligarchic domination. It should be obvious that such line of criticism is not neoliberal, ordoliberal or neo-ordo-liberal. Rather it is a radical critique based on a commitment to equality and solidarity that sets as its target the managerial welfare state, which depletes the solidaristic resources of society.17 Her argument calls, as much as with democracy, to recuperate the solidaristic impulse at the core of any form of social state, including the welfare state, and the techniques and legal technology of mutualism and solidarity. In that regard, the indivisibility of rights emphasises the importance of social cohesion, but renders clear that bread and circus are not only bad replacements of democracy, but that at the end of the day the attachment to bread and circus tends to result in, sooner or later, bread and circus not being there.
14Next to a critique of the welfare state, we find a critical analysis of the concept and figure of the forced migrant as the other symptomatic figure of modern politics. Chapter 6 of Le commun de la liberté traces the obvious parallelism between the two issues, which are in fact just one, in the sense that the closing of the polity results from an exclusionary conception of private property writ large, of citizens being projected as the owners of the polity, and having therefore the faculty of excluding those who are not citizens at will (capitalistic property projected into capitalistic citizenship becomes the ultimate engine of breaking social bonds and pre-empting the creation of new ones). This critique contains, in nuce, a theory of the open and cooperative polity, which has to respond to the federal principle. This has to be interpreted as a strong invitation to consider the institutional arrangements which are part of the “international” dimension of our socio-economic structure (from trade to monetary mechanisms) and to do so with a view to problematise them. Basically the opposite of what became customary during the decades in which the so-called process of globalisation unfolded.
Why a defence of the radical enlightenment is very much needed
15Rights discourses are ubiquitous. We live not so much in the era of rights, as in the era of discourses on rights. Still not infrequently such discourses proceed aloof from their normative justification, emancipated from the matrix of the normative project of the radical enlightenment. Such a state of affairs is extremely dangerous from a normative perspective. It results in a rights theory such as that put forward in Le commun de la liberté being simultaneously attacked from two different flanks, so to say.
- 18 See Q. Slobodian, Crack-Up Capitalism: Market Radicals and the Dream of a World without Democracy, (...)
16First we find those who have tried to hijack the radical enlightenment project and turn it into the normative discourse entrenching the status quo, that is, entrenching the establishment. Conservative renderings of the enlightenment, which assume that it would suffice to change political forms without changing socio-economic realities, are blended into visions embedded in pre-modern understandings. This facilitates the reverse-engineering of the rights project and discourse, so that attacks on equal liberty are clothed in the language of rights. If On the Jewish Question keeps on being a highly relevant text, it is because we are back to a situation in which the right to private property (now specified as the right to free movement of capital) is used to hide in plain sight exploitation (and therefore alienation) through waged labour and through capitalist money. This is the core move underpinning the writings of what we may call the neo-ordo-liberals, the works of Friedrich Hayek, Walter Eucken, Wilhelm Röpke, Robert Nozick or James Buchanan. A rhetoric that is getting more radicalised as time passes, with a resurrection of anarcho-capitalistic discourses.18
- 19 See S. Moyn, Humane: How the United States Abandoned Peace and Reinvented War, New York, Farrar, St (...)
17By the same token, theories of rights, inextricably linked with forms of federalism that deny that war is an intrinsic part of human life, and that permanent (eternal) peace is a feasible project, have been turned upside down and become the very justification of power politics, providing a peculiar new twist to theories of just war (a marriage made in hell between the language of rights and the old doctrines of just war). This was in the making since 1945, but became obvious in the aftermath of the Vietnam War, and operational during the bombing of Kosovo in 1999 and in the run up to the third Iraq War of 2003.19 A similar line of reasoning could be developed regarding how the discourse of rights is being used to oppose that civilisational achievement, even if precarious and insufficient, which is the right of asylum. Instead of an instrument of emancipation, rights discourses run the risk of becoming an instrument at the service of reaction, of counter-revolution. In brief, the source of reasons with which to justify not tackling the injustices characteristic of our socio-economic order. This means that rights have been placed at the service of hierarchy, not autonomy; subordination, not emancipation; exploitation, not liberation. That is a first and fundamental reason to vindicate rights, starting from the denunciation of these instrumental, manipulative, parasitic uses of rights, tendencies clearly at work in the characterisation of the rights of corporations as fundamental rights.
18The reactivation of the radical enlightenment, with bold theories of rights as proposed by Colliot-Thélène in Le commun de la liberté, is especially urgent because the success of this counter-revolutionary offensive clothed in the language of rights has led to the questioning of the very normative project of rights, to the denial of its emancipatory nature. Leading far too many, in academia but also in public discourses, to conclude that the discourses just described do not reflect the manipulative character of the powers to be, but simply the very nature of rights per se. Much as is the case with democratic law, and with the very project of democratic constitutional law, instead of denouncing its manipulation, such manipulation is confused with the very nature of law, the very nature of constitutions, the very nature of rights, prolonging a vulgar and inaccurate Marxist critique against the best (and contextual) interpretation of Marx that Colliot-Thélène offers. Instead of foundational commitments, constitutive of the grammar through which equal liberty can be realised, rights are considered as external constraints through which the “radical potentiality” of democracy is deactivated to be overcome through an unmediated appeal to democratic politics, neglecting the lessons of the various disasters which proved the necessary and indivisible character of civic, political and economic rights. If we had time to engage into some forays in the sociology of knowledge, I would be tempted to relate the theoretical claims made by all these theories which systematically confuse the constitutive character of rights and of the law with external constraints on democratic politics with the social, economic, political and cultural context in which such ideas emerged. I would only say here that at least in some cases, under the appeals to an apparently all powerful and all mighty constituent power (so frequent in so-called post-hegemonic theories), lays the total lack of institutional imagination.
Pushing the argument further
19In this second part of the article, I focus on the ways in which the arguments put forward in Le commun de la liberté can be further developed. In particular, I consider the main outlines of a new conception of property, which in my view needs to take fully into account the normative learning stemming from the constitutional and political practices of new forms of property, but also the extent to which the main object of property nowadays is financial wealth (something which comes hand in hand with a very concrete conception of capitalistic money); by the same token, it is of essence to keep constantly in mind that “bourgeois” property fostered the exploitation of natural resources without proper account being taken of the wider social and ecological implications (which are becoming obviously pressing). Then I put forward some thoughts on how we could reconcile Colliot-Thélène’s insights on the need of going beyond the right to hospitality by means of a renovated understanding of citizenship and other personal statuses. Finally, I consider how Le commun de la liberté requires that we do not only rethink the right to private property and personal statuses, but also that we consider anew the very concept of rights, and in particular, why we need a conception of fundamental rights positions which is not limited to subjective rights, but encompasses collective rights and collective goods.
A new property
20As was already underlined in the first section of this article, a central thesis of Le commun de la liberté is that we need to radically change the way we imagine and conceptualise property, in particular transcending “bourgeois property”. If that is the pars destruens of Le commun de la liberté, its pars construens concerns the imagination of a form of property which is not at the service of accumulation through expropriation, but rather can function as the key point of access to the commons with a view to satisfy the material needs of human beings. A property-freedom which can be a pillar of a truly democratic political order.
- 20 G. Kennedy, Diggers, Levellers and Agrarian Capitalism: Radical Political Thought in Seventeenth Ce (...)
- 21 O. Chaïbi, Proudhon et la banque du peuple: 1848-1849, Paris, Connaissances et savoirs, 2010.
- 22 M. Goldmann, A. J. Menéndez, “Weimar Moments: Transformations of the Democratic, Social, and Open S (...)
21As already pointed, Le commun de la liberté offers a combined reading of Marx and Kant, but it seems to me it is worth placing the book in the wider context of the 19th and 20th-century works of political philosophy which aim at finding an alternative conception of property (and of money). To put it differently, property has been more frequently reimagined that we have dared to think. Therefore a key part of the new theorising of property must consist in taking systematic stock of the political and moral knowledge implicit in such practices. Among the less frequently considered reference points, I would mention the levellers and the diggers in the English Revolution20 and Proudhon, to whom I have already made references in this article. Next to his memoirs on property and his Théorie de la propriété, it is high time we read in earnest his fundamental writings on money and on the “bank of the people”.21 But we have to consider not only a number of social movements and authors, but also the collective moral knowledge, if I am allowed the expression, reflected in the 20th-century constitutions which are part of the long Weimar constitutional moment.22 To summarise such practices is impossible in this article. What can be done is to consider the two axes around which such new practices have emerged. The first concerns the redefinition of property as a relationship between persons which has implications for the allocation of rights over goods, instead of a relation between the property owner and the objects of property. This change of focus is fundamental if we want to incorporate the key insights of the constitutional doctrine of the “social function of property”, or the affirmation of the importance of the eminent domain of the polity over the key sources of wealth in a given socio-economic structure. The second axis concerns the need of taking systematic stock of the legal techniques through which property has been geared towards the commons, not least through the drastic limitation of the “absolute” character of property by means of increasing the number of those with different claims on property objects (think about co-determination practices in the government of enterprises), and the limitation of the “savage” powers of the property owner (from the control of movements of capital to the setting of limits to inheritance or designing forms of money with an expiry date).
- 23 Joseph Alois Schumpeter’s hero was a man from the corporation, even if an exceptional individual; o (...)
- 24 C. Lapavitsas, Marxist Monetary Theory, New York, Haymarket Books, 2017.
- 25 C. Lapavitsas, Profiting without Producing: How Finance Exploits Us All, London, Verso, 2013.
- 26 S. Eich, The Currency of Politics: The Political Theory of Money from Aristotle to Keynes, Princeto (...)
22But there is more. The very “phenomenology” of money has changed, for the simple reason that capitalist property is now, above all, financial property. True, the transformation is far from completely new. By the time that Marx painfully published the first volume of Das Kapital (1867), the legal technology of the société anonyme was no longer exceptional, and had become the decisive form through which capital organised itself. The myth of the individual entrepreneur persisted, albeit radically transformed, as the captain of an organisation, of, indeed, a corporation.23 Such corporations became the materially decisive dramatis personae of the economic play. By the same token, finance was at the core of Marx’s analysis, and indeed contemporary Marxists analyses of money take cue from the (less studied) Marx’s writings on the subject.24 What was a trend in the last third of the 19th century has become a state of affairs impossible to miss now, with the majority of wealth being clearly financial and money transformed into fully fiat money (since the dollar, the world reserve currency was definitely de-anchored from gold in 1971 and the creation of money has largely been privatised through the deregulation of financial institutions). Political theory needs to think through all the implications these changes have. In critical terms to the extent that, while there is no doubt that exploitation through waged-labour remains a very tangible reality, exploitation through financial mediation and through the very processes through which capital gets invested has become a decisive way in which capital breeds capital.25 We need to rethink money alongside property.26
- 27 We have wasted decades in that regard. See letter from Sicco Mansholt to Franco Maria Malfatti (Feb (...)
23Finally, there is one topic which Colliot-Thélène only touches en passant, and which however seems to me to be pressing to incorporate to any radically enlightened conception of property. Namely the relationship between the preservation of the environment (essential for the continuation of the human experiment on earth) and property. If the democratic and social state entails a move from the individual to the person, in full respect of normative individualism, we are in urgent need of adding to that person a clear normative profile which defines her relationship with nature (which is, no doubt, a most debated concept in philosophical terms). I have some doubts that this can be done merely by means of extending rights to animals, or to all living beings, or to the Earth as such (although this is not unprecedented, think for example about the Constitution of Bolivia). The question is not an easy one, but it seems to me that we run the risk of losing more by extending too quickly the holdership of rights to the environment and to animals than what we would gain by doing so. What matters is that climate change is a powerful reminder of the finite character of the planet, and the very tangible limits that there are to a relationship of human beings in balance and equilibrium with our natural environment. It seems to me that a radical enlightened conception of property has to take sides with (happy) degrowth, insisting on the need of taking very seriously the distributional justice of slowing down the use of natural resources.27
A new citizenship
- 28 C. Colliot-Thélène, Le commun de la liberté…, p. 228.
- 29 This is clearly the policy favoured by the European Union. See for example the so-called “EU-Turkey (...)
- 30 D. Kochenov, Citizenship, Cambridge, MIT Press, 2019.
24Democracy without the demos is a matter of (equal) rights.28 Rights which are contradicted by bourgeois property, which, as a pointed, is a form of property-theft: the homeless, the riders, the kellys are the most obvious victims (but not the only ones) of exploitation through property. But this “internal” form of exclusion is matched by massive exclusionary policies, so as to keep les damnés de la terre away. The right of asylum has become the fig leaf through which we pretend to care for others, but even when forced migrants fully qualify as refugees we try to keep them away through different forms of outsourcing,29 at the cheapest possible market price. Does that entail that democracy without the demos requires abolishing citizenship?30
25The answer, it seems to me, must be negative.
- 31 C. Castoriadis, Sur “Le politique” de Platon, Paris, Seuil, 1999.
26Only if we defend and reinforce citizenship we can realise the (political) value of self-government. This is a key intuition that we find in the Greek conception of citizenship as described by Aristotle, one that remains valid.31 Without strong citizenship, without a focus on political rights to democratic participation, where politics and law are regarded as the mere implementation of a divine will, or understood as the province of the will of rulers legitimised by their charisma, by their knowledge, or by their capacity to generate material wealth, not only self-government comes to an end, but the fate of the forced migrants is bound to be dire.
- 32 É. Lambert, Le gouvernement des juges et la lutte contre la législation sociale aux États-Unis. L’e (...)
- 33 M. García Pelayo, Derecho Constitucional Comparado, Madrid, Revista de Occidente, 1950, chapter 3.
27Indeed, only a democratic and social citizenship can ensure the actual indivisibility of civic, political and social rights. These rights are not only more than mere isolated units to be aggregated, but they are an integral part to the democratic order. Only a community where civic, political and social rights are acknowledged equal dignity and force is genuinely democratic in character. Indeed, without social rights, participatory democracy not only remains a hollow principle, but runs the risk of being “disfigured”. There is no “pure” state of law, but only the democratic and social state is a genuine “state of law”.32 Moreover, democratic and social citizenship is not only about political rights, but about democratic practices of politics. Democratic and social citizenship emerged as a result of very specific and concrete historical conflicts, critically including wars, revolutions, and struggles for inclusion of minorities and excluded groups. In other words, it is not practical reason as such that brought us the eight-hour working day, universal suffrage, the due process of law, or equality between men and women. We owe the key elements of the democratic and social state to social movements, to the women and men that organised, demonstrated and fought for such rights.33
28Therefore, democratic politics, which is required by a radical enlightened politico-philosophical vision, cannot proceed without the integrative force of democratic citizenship. Is democratic politics bound, however, to be exclusionary? Does it entail (re)introducing through the back door the “mask” of the demos?
- 34 H. Kelsen, Der Staats Als Integration, Vienna, Springer, 1930.
- 35 I. S. Patel, We’re Here Because You Were There: Immigration and the End of Empire, London, Verso, 2 (...)
29Not really. Democratic politics needs to be constantly oscillating between moments of unity (in which we make up the collective through common engagement in deliberation about the common good) and moments of plurality, in which we take fully on board the fact that the society and the polity are made of individuals who have specific interests, concerns and views. From a normative perspective, such unity should not be regarded as pre-political, but legally structured and maintained, as indeed Hans Kelsen perceptively insisted.34 Moreover, no clarity is gained by stretching the concept of citizenship so as to cover personal statuses which do not entail rights to be part of the political life of the community. We need to consider the differences between citizenship and other personal statuses, including permanent residence, residence and asylum. Now, there are imperative reasons why a political community should recognise such statuses, especially the latter. Indeed, it is not only the case that on their existence may hinge the justice and fairness of the way in which the political community treats non-citizens, but that some of such statuses (think about the very concept of person as a legal concept) are logically and normatively prior to that of citizenship. But nothing is gained by labelling them as “quasi-citizenship” or by speaking of degrees of citizenship. What we need, on the contrary, are two things. First, the development of a proper federal political theory which dilucidates how to build a political order that covers the entire world but is built from the bottom up, not the reverse, and which would clarify the degree to which the illusion of materially and normatively self-sufficient polities is simply out of synch with the way in which we engage into social and economic relations. The second is a strong sense of the obligations we have to “others” and a clear understanding that the extent to which we discharge such obligations determines who we are. Such obligations result both from special relations stemming from past relationships (such as colonialism, imperialism and neo-imperalism)35 and from general obligations having to do with the very fact of our sharing the earth with all other human beings.
A new theory of rights
- 36 T. H. Marshall, Citizenship and Social Class and Other Essays, Cambridge, Cambridge University Pres (...)
- 37 R. Alexy, “Individual Rights and Collective Goods”, in Rights, C. Santiago Nino (ed.), New York, Ne (...)
30The realisation of equality is only possible if the constitutional grammar is adapted to the requirements of formal equality and material equality. In this respect, it is essential to avoid reducing fundamental legal positions, fundamental rights, to subjective rights. The point is not to undervalue subjective rights, as all reactionary ideologies of the 19th and 20th centuries did (and as contemporary reactionaries, posing as progressives, do). On the contrary. Subjective rights are and must be an integral part of any constitution of freedom: they need to be placed right at the center of any democratic theory which aspires to be susceptible of being characterised as radically enlightened. However, alongside subjective rights, any democratic and social state must recognise the importance of collective rights: not only in the field of labour and industrial relations, but also as a democratic pillar (think of the right of assembly, the right to demonstrate or the right to vote, which comprise both subjective and collective rights). In turn, the substrate on which the effectiveness of both subjective and collective rights is based is collective goods.36 This is because all fundamental rights are complex bundles of legal positions, which presuppose institutional structures dependent on the maintenance of collective goods.37 Indeed, overcoming the centrality of bourgeois property should also mean going beyond the identification of such right to private property as the template on which all other fundamental rights positions should be modelled.
Notes
1 P.-J. Proudhon, Théorie de la propriété, Paris, L’Harmattan, 1997, p. 50.
2 C. Colliot-Thélène, Le commun de la liberté. Du droit de propriété au devoir d’hospitalité, Paris, Presses universitaires de France, 2022.
3 C. Colliot-Thélène, La démocratie sans “demos”, Paris, Presses universitaires de France, 2011.
4 Ibid., p. 10.
5 J. Israel, A Revolution of the Mind: Radical Enlightenment and the Intellectual Origins of Modern Democracy, Princeton, Princeton University Press, 2010.
6 C. Colliot-Thélène, Le commun de la liberté…, p. 11 (all translations are mine).
7 See F. D’Agostino, Chomsky’s System of Ideas, Oxford, Clarendon, 1986, p. 11-12.
8 Also, as we will see, citizenship without ethnos, and property without capitalism and without capitalists, ultimate corollaries of the train of reasoning put forward in the two books.
9 C. Colliot-Thélène, Le commun de la liberté…, p. 61.
10 Ibid., p. 68.
11 See paradigmatically N. MacCormick, “Children’s Rights: A Test-Case for Theories of Right”, ARSP: Archiv für Rechts- und Sozialphilosophie / Archives for Philosophy of Law and Social Philosophy, vol. 62, no. 3, 1976, p. 305-317.
12 A. Shachar, The Birthright Lottery: Citizenship and Global Inequality, Cambridge, Harvard University Press, 2009. In the first chapter, Schahar gives an account of the different ways in which the rules of access to citizenship at birth contribute to global inequality, while in the sixth chapter she puts forward an alternative model (“jus nexi”) which would be much preferable. Still, it remains the case that the ultimate cause of the inequalities is not citizenship as such, but rather the underlying socio-economic structure, including the unavoidable creation and recreation of cores and peripheries.
13 C. Colliot-Thélène, Le commun de la liberté…, p. 136. The term “cannibal capitalism”, of Weberian and Polanyian lineage, is due to N. Fraser, Cannibal Capitalism, How Our System Is Devouring Democracy, Care and the Planet – And What We Can Do about It, London, Verso, 2022.
14 J. Locke, Two Treatises of Government [1689], P. Laslett (ed.), Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1988, p. 285-302.
15 R. Nozick, Anarchy, State and Utopia, New York, Basic Books, 1974, chapter 7. For the right-based character of the theory, see above all chapter 1.
16 C. Colliot-Thélène, Le commun de la liberté…, p. 155 sq.
17 For a similar critique of the welfare state as a managerial device which ends up licencing corporate capitalism, without renouncing a strong commitment to egalitarianism, see J. Rawls, A Theory of Justice, Cambridge, Harvard University Press, 1971, p. 265 sq. and, above all, J. Rawls, Justice as Fairness: A Restatement, E. Kelly (ed.), Cambridge, Harvard University Press, 2001.
18 See Q. Slobodian, Crack-Up Capitalism: Market Radicals and the Dream of a World without Democracy, London, Allen Lane, 2023. Javier Milei, now president of Argentina, outstands in his reproposing of anarcho-capitalist trains of reasoning. See his speech of January 18th, 2024, online: https://www.weforum.org/agenda/2024/01/special-address-by-javier-milei-president-of-argentina.
19 See S. Moyn, Humane: How the United States Abandoned Peace and Reinvented War, New York, Farrar, Straus and Giroux, 2022.
20 G. Kennedy, Diggers, Levellers and Agrarian Capitalism: Radical Political Thought in Seventeenth Century England, Lanham, Lexington Books, 2008.
21 O. Chaïbi, Proudhon et la banque du peuple: 1848-1849, Paris, Connaissances et savoirs, 2010.
22 M. Goldmann, A. J. Menéndez, “Weimar Moments: Transformations of the Democratic, Social, and Open State of Law”, Max Planck Institute for Comparative Public Law and International Law (MPIL), Research Paper no. 2022-12, online: https://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=4141137.
23 Joseph Alois Schumpeter’s hero was a man from the corporation, even if an exceptional individual; oddly enough, what was needed was not so much scientific knowledge, technical knowledge, as the skill and art of ruling others, as much as was needed in the case of the politicians which the crowd will elect in the British inspired minimalist understanding of democracy (J. A. Schumpeter, Capitalism, Socialism and Democracy, paperback edition, New York, Harper and Row, 1975, p. 132).
24 C. Lapavitsas, Marxist Monetary Theory, New York, Haymarket Books, 2017.
25 C. Lapavitsas, Profiting without Producing: How Finance Exploits Us All, London, Verso, 2013.
26 S. Eich, The Currency of Politics: The Political Theory of Money from Aristotle to Keynes, Princeton, Princeton University Press, 2022.
27 We have wasted decades in that regard. See letter from Sicco Mansholt to Franco Maria Malfatti (February 1972), online: https://www.cvce.eu/en/obj/letter_from_sicco_mansholt_to_franco_maria_malfatti_february_1972-en-51303966-0532-46bc-89c7-271ef294eb13.html. See also K. Saitō, Slow Down: The Degrowth Manifesto [1998], B. Bergstrom (trans.), New York, Astra House, 2024 and A. Turiel, Petrocalipsis: Crisis energética global y cómo (no) la vamos a solucionar, Madrid, Alfabeto Editorial, 2020.
28 C. Colliot-Thélène, Le commun de la liberté…, p. 228.
29 This is clearly the policy favoured by the European Union. See for example the so-called “EU-Turkey Statement” of March 18th, 2016, online: https://www.consilium.europa.eu/en/press/press-releases/2016/03/18/eu-turkey-statement. This technology has been copied by many other countries. See the Safety of Rwanda (Asylum and Immigration) Bill, online: https://publications.parliament.uk/pa/bills/cbill/58-04/0038/230038.pdf; see also the UK-Rwanda Agreement on an Asylum Partnership, online: https://committees.parliament.uk/publications/42927/documents/213461/default.
30 D. Kochenov, Citizenship, Cambridge, MIT Press, 2019.
31 C. Castoriadis, Sur “Le politique” de Platon, Paris, Seuil, 1999.
32 É. Lambert, Le gouvernement des juges et la lutte contre la législation sociale aux États-Unis. L’expérience américaine du contrôle judiciaire de la constitutionnalité des lois, Paris, M. Giard, 1921; H. Heller, “Political Democracy and Social Homogeneity” [1928], in Weimar. A Jurisprudence of Crisis, A. J. Jacobson, B. Schlink (eds.), B. Cooper (trans.), Berkeley, University of California Press, 2000, p. 256-265.
33 M. García Pelayo, Derecho Constitucional Comparado, Madrid, Revista de Occidente, 1950, chapter 3.
34 H. Kelsen, Der Staats Als Integration, Vienna, Springer, 1930.
35 I. S. Patel, We’re Here Because You Were There: Immigration and the End of Empire, London, Verso, 2022.
36 T. H. Marshall, Citizenship and Social Class and Other Essays, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1950; C. Bec, La Sécurité sociale: une institution de la démocratie, Paris, Gallimard, 2014.
37 R. Alexy, “Individual Rights and Collective Goods”, in Rights, C. Santiago Nino (ed.), New York, New York University Press, 1992, p. 163-181.
Haut de pagePour citer cet article
Référence papier
Agustín José Menéndez, « Rights beyond the Unencumbered Self: Property-Freedom and Federation against Property-Theft and Centralisation », Cahiers de philosophie de l’université de Caen, 61 | 2024, 49-64.
Référence électronique
Agustín José Menéndez, « Rights beyond the Unencumbered Self: Property-Freedom and Federation against Property-Theft and Centralisation », Cahiers de philosophie de l’université de Caen [En ligne], 61 | 2024, mis en ligne le 21 juin 2024, consulté le 23 janvier 2025. URL : http://0-journals-openedition-org.catalogue.libraries.london.ac.uk/cpuc/3385 ; DOI : https://0-doi-org.catalogue.libraries.london.ac.uk/10.4000/11vse
Haut de pageDroits d’auteur
Le texte seul est utilisable sous licence CC BY-NC 4.0. Les autres éléments (illustrations, fichiers annexes importés) sont « Tous droits réservés », sauf mention contraire.
Haut de page